A parole board considers the release of a prisoner: Will he be violent again? A hiring officer considers a job candidate: Will she be a valuable asset to the company? A young couple considers marriage: Will they have a happy marriage?

The cached wisdom for making such high-stakes predictions is to have experts gather as much evidence as possible, weigh this evidence, and make a judgment. But 60 years of research has shown that in hundreds of cases, a simple formula called a statistical prediction rule (SPR) makes better predictions than leading experts do. Or, more exactly:

When based on the same evidence, the predictions of SPRs are at least as reliable as, and are typically more reliable than, the predictions of human experts for problems of social prediction.1

For example, one SPR developed in 1995 predicts the price of mature Bordeaux red wines at auction better than expert wine tasters do. Reaction from the wine-tasting industry to such wine-predicting SPRs has been "somewhere between violent and hysterical."

How does the SPR work? This particular SPR is called a proper linear model, which has the form:

P = w1(c1) + w2(c2) + w3(c3) + ...wn(cn)

The model calculates the summed result P, which aims to predict a target property such as wine price, on the basis of a series of cues. Above, cn is the value of the nth cue, and wn is the weight assigned to the nth cue.2

In the wine-predicting SPR, c1 reflects the age of the vintage, and other cues reflect relevant climatic features where the grapes were grown. The weights for the cues were assigned on the basis of a comparison of these cues to a large set of data on past market prices for mature Bordeaux wines.3

There are other ways to construct SPRs, but rather than survey these details, I will instead survey the incredible success of SPRs.

  • Howard and Dawes (1976) found they can reliably predict marital happiness with one of the simplest SPRs ever conceived, using only two cues: P = [rate of lovemaking] - [rate of fighting]. The reliability of this SPR was confirmed by Edwards & Edwards (1977) and by Thornton (1979).
  • Unstructured interviews reliably degrade the decisions of gatekeepers (e.g. hiring and admissions officers, parole boards, etc.). Gatekeepers (and SPRs) make better decisions on the basis of dossiers alone than on the basis of dossiers and unstructured interviews. (Bloom and Brundage 1947, DeVaul et. al. 1957, Oskamp 1965, Milstein et. al. 1981; Hunter & Hunter 1984; Wiesner & Cronshaw 1988). If you're hiring, you're probably better off not doing interviews.
  • Wittman (1941) constructed an SPR that predicted the success of electroshock therapy for patients more reliably than the medical or psychological staff.
  • Carroll et. al. (1988) found an SPR that predicts criminal recidivism better than expert criminologists.
  • An SPR constructed by Goldberg (1968) did a better job of diagnosing patients as neurotic or psychotic than did trained clinical psychologists.
  • SPRs regularly predict academic performance better than admissions officers, whether for medical schools (DeVaul et. al. 1957), law schools (Swets, Dawes and Monahan 2000), or graduate school in psychology (Dawes 1971).
  • SPRs predict loan and credit risk better than bank officers (Stillwell et. al. 1983).
  • SPRs predict newborns at risk for Sudden Infant Death Syndrome better than human experts do (Lowry 1975; Carpenter et. al. 1977; Golding et. al. 1985).
  • SPRs are better at predicting who is prone to violence than are forensic psychologists (Faust & Ziskin 1988).
  • Libby (1976) found a simple SPR that predicted firm bankruptcy better than experienced loan officers.

And that is barely scratching the surface.

If this is not amazing enough, consider the fact that even when experts are given the results of SPRs, they still can't outperform those SPRs (Leli & Filskov 1985; Goldberg 1968).

So why aren't SPRs in use everywhere? Probably, suggest Bishop & Trout, we deny or ignore the success of SPRs because of deep-seated cognitive biases, such as overconfidence in our own judgments. But if these SPRs work as well as or better than human judgments, shouldn't we use them?

Robyn Dawes (2002) drew out the normative implications of such studies:

If a well-validated SPR that is superior to professional judgment exists in a relevant decision making context, professionals should use it, totally absenting themselves from the prediction.

Sometimes, being rational is easy. When there exists a reliable statistical prediction rule for the problem you're considering, you need not waste your brain power trying to make a careful judgment. Just take an outside view and use the damn SPR.4

 

 

Recommended Reading

 

Notes

1 Bishop & Trout, Epistemology and the Psychology of Human Judgment, p. 27. The definitive case for this claim is made in a 1996 study by Grove & Meehl that surveyed 136 studies yielding 617 comparisons between the judgments of human experts and SPRs (in which humans and SPRs made predictions about the same cases and the SPRs never had more information than the humans). Grove & Meehl found that of the 136 studies, 64 favored the SPR, 64 showed roughly equal accuracy, and 8 favored human judgment. Since these last 8 studies "do not form a pocket of predictive excellent in which [experts] could profitably specialize," Grove and Meehl speculated that these 8 outliers may be due to random sampling error.

2 Readers of Less Wrong may recognize SPRs as a relatively simple type of expert system.

3 But, see Anatoly_Vorobey's fine objections.

4 There are occasional exceptions, usually referred to as "broken leg" cases. Suppose an SPR reliably predicts an individual's movie attendance, but then you learn he has a broken leg. In this case it may be wise to abandon the SPR. The problem is that there is no general rule for when experts should abandon the SPR. When they are allowed to do so, they abandon the SPR far too frequently, and thus would have been better off sticking strictly to the SPR, even for legitimate "broken leg" instances (Goldberg 1968; Sawyer 1966; Leli and Filskov 1984).

 

References

Bloom & Brundage (1947). "Predictions of Success in Elementary School for Enlisted Personnel", Personnel Research and Test Development in the Natural Bureau of Personnel, ed. D.B. Stuit, 233-61. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Carpenter, Gardner, McWeeny, & Emery (1977). "Multistage scory systemfor identifying infants at risk of unexpected death", Arch. Dis. Childh., 53: 606−612.

Carroll, Winer, Coates, Galegher, & Alibrio (1988). "Evaluation, Diagnosis, and Prediction in Parole Decision-Making", Law and Society Review, 17: 199-228.

Dawes (1971). "A Case Study of Graduate Admissions: Applications of Three Principles of Human Decision-Making", American Psychologist, 26: 180-88.

Dawes (2002). "The Ethics of Using or Not Using Statistical Prediction Rules in Psychological Practice and Related Consulting Activities", Philosophy of Science, 69: S178-S184.

DeVaul, Jervey, Chappell, Carver, Short, & O'Keefe (1957). "Medical School Performance of Initially Rejected Students", Journal of the American Medical Association, 257: 47-51.

Faust & Ziskin (1988). "The expert witness in psychology and psychiatry", Science, 241: 1143−1144.

Goldberg (1968). "Simple Models of Simple Process? Some Research on Clinical Judgments", American Psychologist, 23: 483-96.

Golding, Limerick, & MacFarlane (1985). Sudden Infant Death. Somerset: Open Books.

Edwards & Edwards (1977). "Marriage: Direct and Continuous Measurement", Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 10: 187-88.

Howard & Dawes (1976). "Linear Prediction of Marital Happiness", Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 2: 478-80.

Hunter & Hunter (1984). "Validity and utility of alternate predictors of job performance", Psychological Bulletin, 96: 72-98

Leli & Filskov (1984). "Clinical Detection of Intellectual Deterioration Associated with Brain Damage", Journal of Clinical Psychology, 40: 1435–1441.

Libby (1976). "Man versus model of man: Some conflicting evidence", Organizational Behavior and Human Performance, 16: 1-12.

Lowry (1975). "The identification of infants at high risk of early death", Med. Stats. Report, London School of Hygiene and Tropical Medicine.

Milstein, Wildkinson, Burrow, & Kessen (1981). "Admission Decisions and Performance during Medical School", Journal of Medical Education, 56: 77-82.

Oskamp (1965). "Overconfidence in Case Study Judgments", Journal of Consulting Psychology, 63: 81-97.

Sawyer (1966). "Measurement and Prediction, Clinical and Statistical", Psychological Bulletin, 66: 178-200.

Stillwell, Barron, & Edwards (1983). "Evaluating Credit Applications: A Validation of Multiattribute Utility Weight Elicitation Techniques", Organizational Behavior and Human Performance, 32: 87-108.

Swets, Dawes, & Monahan (2000). "Psychological Science Can Improve Diagnostic Decisions", Psychological Science in the Public Interest, 1: 1–26.

Thornton (1977). "Linear Prediction of Marital Happiness: A Replication", Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 3: 674-76.

Wiesner & Cronshaw (1988). "A meta-analytic investigation of the impact of interview format and degree of structure on the validity of the employment interview", Journal of Applied Psychology, 61: 275-290.

Wittman (1941). "A Scale for Measuring Prognosis in Schizophrenic Patients", Elgin Papers 4: 20-33.

Statistical Prediction Rules Out-Perform Expert Human Judgments
New Comment
199 comments, sorted by Click to highlight new comments since:
Some comments are truncated due to high volume. (⌘F to expand all)Change truncation settings

I'm skeptical, and will now proceed to question some of the assertions made/references cited. Note that I'm not trained in statistics.

Unfortunately, most of the articles cited are not easily available. I would have liked to check the methodology of a few more of them.

For example, one SPR developed in 1995 predicts the price of mature Bordeaux red wines at auction better than expert wine tasters do.

The paper doesn't actually establish what you say it does. There is no statistical analysis of expert wine tasters, only one or two anecdotal statements of their fury at the whole idea. Instead, the SPR is compared to actual market prices - not to experts' predictions. I think it's fair to say that the claim I quoted is overreached.

Now, about the model and its fit to data. Note that the SPR is older than 1995, when the paper was published. The NYTimes article about it which you reference is from 1990 (the paper bizarrely dates it to 1995; I'm not sure what's going on there).

The fact that there's a linear model - not specified precisely anywhere in the article - which is a good fit to wine prices for vintages of 1961-1972 (Table 3 in the paper) is not, I think, very significant on its... (read more)

If you're hiring, you're probably better off not doing interviews.

My own experience strongly suggests to me that this claim is inane - and is highly dangerous advice... My personal experience from interviewing many, many candidates for a large company suggests that interviewing is crucial (though I will freely grant that different kinds of interviews vary wildly in their effectiveness).

The whole point of this article is that experts often think themselves better than SPR's when actually they perform no better than SPRs on average. Here we have an expert telling us that he thinks he would perform better than an SPR. Why should we be interested?

Because I didn't just state a blanket opinion. I dug into the studies, looked for data to test one of them in depth, and found it to be highly flawed. I called into question the methodology employed by the studies, as well as overgeneralizing and overreaching conclusions they're drummed up to support. The evidence that at least some studies are flawed and the methodology is shoddy should make you question the universal claim "... actually they perform no better than SPRs on average". That's why you should be interested.

My personal experience with interviewing is certainly not as important piece of evidence against the article as the specific criticisms of the studies. It's just another anecdotal data point. That's why I didn't expand on it as much as I did on the wine study, although I do believe it can be made more convincing through further elucidation.

My own experience strongly suggests to me that this claim is inane ... it would only follow if you believe yourself to be no more competent than the average hiring manager in such a body, or in the papers you reference.

What evidence do you have that you are better than average?

My personal experience from interviewing many, many candidates for a large company suggests that interviewing is crucial

"It is difficult to get a man to understand something, when his salary depends upon his not understanding it!"

4Desrtopa
I have heard of one job interview that I felt constituted a useful tool that could not effectively be replaced by resume examination and statistical analysis. A friend of mine got a job working for a company that provides mathematical modeling services for other companies, and his "interview" was a several hour test to create a number of mathematical models, and then explaining to the examiner in layman's terms how and why the models worked. Most job interviews are really not a demonstration of job skills and aptitude, and it's possible to simply bullshit your way through them. On the other hand, if you have a simple and direct way to test the competence of your applicants, then by all means use it.

I'm most familiar with interviews for programming jobs, where an interview that doesn't ask the candidate to demonstrate job-specific skills, knowledge and aptitude is nearly worthless. These jobs are also startlingly prone to resume distortion that can make vastly different candidates look similar, especially recent graduates.

Asking for coding samples and calling previous employers, especially if coupled with a request for code solving a new (requested) problem, could potentially replace interviews. However, judging the quality of code still requires a person, so that doesn't seem to really change things to me.

1sketerpot
That's what I think of, too, when I hear the phrase "job interview". Is this not typical outside fields like programming?

I can confirm that such a "job interview" is not common in medicine. The potential employer generally relies on the credentialing process of the medical establishment. Most physicians, upon completing their training, pass a test demonstrating their ability to regurgitate the teachers' passwords, and are recommended to the appropriate certification board as "qualified" by their program director; to do otherwise would reflect badly on the program. Also, program directors are loath to remove a resident/fellow during advanced training because some warm body must show up to do the work, or the professor himself/herself might have to fill in. It is difficult to find replacements for upper level residents; the only common reason such would be available is dismissal/transfer from another program. Consequently, the USA turns out physicians of widely varied skill levels, even though their credentials are similar. In surgical specialities, it is not unusual for a particularly bright individual with all the passwords but very poor technical skills to become a surgical professor.

4Desrtopa
My mother has told me an anecdote about a family friend who was a surgeon who had a former student call him while conducting an operation because he couldn't remember what to do.

My mother has told me an anecdote about a family friend who was a surgeon who had a former student call him while conducting an operation because he couldn't remember what to do.

The (rumored) student has my respect. I would expect most surgeons to have too much of an ego to admit to that doubt rather than stumble ahead full of hubris. It would be comforting to know that your surgeon acted as if (as opposed to merely believing that) he cared more about the patient than the immediate perception of status loss. (I wouldn't care whether that just meant his thought out anticipation of future status loss for a failed operation overrode his immediate social instincts.)

[-]knb100

That isn't an interview, it's a test. Tests are extremely useful. IQ tests are an excellent predictor of job performance, maybe the best one available. Regardless, IQ tests are usually de facto illegal in the US due to disparate impact.

4Desrtopa
I put interview in quotes because they called it an interview. Speaking broadly enough, all interviews are tests, but most are unstructured and not very good at examining the relevant predictor variables. All tests are of course not necessarily interviews, but the part where they had applicants explain their processes in layman's terms might qualify it, at least if you're generous with your definitions. Of course, it's certainly unclear if not outright incorrect to call it an interview, but that was their choice; possibly they felt that subjecting applicants to a "test" rather than an "interview" projected a less positive image.
2Dr_Manhattan
I don't think it's fair, as his job is not being an interviewer, but perhaps hiring smart people we can benefit from.
9lukeprog
Cool, I'll look into these points. I made one small change so far. The above article now read: "Reaction from the wine-tasting industry to such wine-predicting SPRs has been 'somewhere between violent and hysterical.'" Also, I'll post links to the specific papers when I have time to visit UCLA and grab them. Psychology is not my field, but my understanding is that the 'interview effect' for unstructured interviews is a very robust finding across many decades. For more, you can listen to my interview with Michael Bishop. But hey, maybe he's wrong! Update 1: If I read the 1995 study correctly, they judged the accuracy of wine tasters by comparing the price of immature wines to those of mature wines, but I'm not sure. The way I phrased that is from Bishop & Trout, and that is how Bishop recalls it, though it's been several years now since he co-wrote Epistemology and the Psychology of Human Judgment.
2CronoDAS
Regarding hiring, I think the keyword might be "unstructured" - what makes an interview an "unstructured" interview?

That's what I thought too. The definitions I found searching all say that any interview where you decide what to ask and how to interpret the results is "unstructured". The only "structured" interviews seem to be tests with pre-determined sets of questions, and the candidate's answers judged by formal criteria.

I'm not sure this division of the "interview-space" is all that useful. I would distinguish three categories:

  1. You have an informat chat with me about the nature of the job, my experience, my previous employment, my claims about my aptitude, etc. Your impressions from this chat determine your judgement of my suitability for the job.
  2. You ask me to answer questions or perform tasks that demonstrate my aptitude. It's up to you to choose the tasks, interpret my performance, and guide the whole process.
  3. You give me a pre-determined set of questions/tasks that is the same for all candidates. My answers are mechanically interpreted by whether they coincide with the pre-determined set of correct answers.

If I interpret the definitions I could find correctly, 3 is a "structured" interview, and both 1 and 2 are "unstructured". To my ... (read more)

1XiXiDu
The interview example makes sense to me if the usual hiring manager is strongly biased regarding information that are not crucial. A dossier only gives little but important information. In a face-to-face interview various other factors can play a role (often unconsciously), e.g. smell or the ability to return a look.
-2[anonymous]
More here. Surely that isn't strong evidence but another indication that if you are not an LW type person then information that are not crucial might alter your perception and subsequent decision when doing face-to-face interviews versus dossier based ruling.
0shokwave
Read the Dawes pdf linked in the top post. I can't speak for the other examples, but that one is solid. edit: my apologies, re-reading I see you discussed the marriage example. What is your opinion on the graduate rating and Hodgkin's disease examples?
9Perplexed
Why do you say that? My reaction to that paper was very negative. In large part, it was the anecdotal flavor of the arguments made there, but also because I didn't see the two things I was specifically looking for: * Citations of studies in which a linear model was constructed using one set of data, and then compared as to performance against the experts using a different set of data. * Failing that, some numbers that would convince me that the failure to test models using different data than was used to construct them just doesn't matter. Instead, here and in the 1996 study by Grove & Meehl, I find arguments from incredulity - in effect: "Do our critics really think that this really matters? Don't be absurd!". I also notice that this ideology is being promoted by a small number of researchers who repeatedly cite each other's work, and do not cite critics (except as strawmen).
7DanielVarga
Like Perplexed, I hated this paper. Of course, it has the very good excuse that it is from 1979. But in 2011, it is sort of expected that you evaluate your model on a second, independent dataset. (My models often crash and burn at this stage.) Did any of these studies do this?

Also, if I may be permitted to make a more general criticism in response to this post, I would say that while the article appears to be well-researched, it has demonstrated some of the worst problems I commonly notice on this forum. The same goes for the majority of the comments, even though many are knowledgeable and informative. What I have in mind is the fixation on concocting theories about human behavior and society based on various idées fixes and leitmotifs that are parts of the intellectual folklore here, while failing to notice issues suggested by basic common sense that are likely to be far more important.

Thus the poster notices that these models are not used in practice despite considerable evidence in their favor, and rushes to propose cognitive biases à la Kahneman & Tversky as the likely explanation. This without even stopping to think of two questions that just scream for attention. First, what is the importance of the fact that just about any issue of sorting out people is nowadays likely to be ideologically charged and legally dangerous? Second, what about the fact that these models are supposed to throw some high-status people out of work, and in a way that m... (read more)

9lukeprog
My intent was to summarize the literature on SPRs, not provide an account for why they are not used more widely. I almost didn't include that sentence at all. Surely, more analysis would be important to have in a post intending to discuss the psychological issues involved in our reaction to SPRs, but that was not my subject. In pointing to cognitive biases as an explanation, I was merely repeating what Bishop & Trout & Dawes have suggested on the matter, not making up my own explanations in light of LW lore. In fact, the arrows point the other way. Many of the authors cited in my article worked closely with people like Kahneman who are the original academic sources of much of LW lore. Edit: I've added a clause about the source of the "cognitive biases" suggestion, in case others are tempted to make the same mistaken assumption as you made.
7Miller
While this post has +40 upvotes, the majority of the top-voted comments are skeptical of it. I think this represents confusion as to how to upvote, although this is merely a hypothesis. The article surveys a very interesting topic that is right in the sweet spot of interest for this community, it also appears scholarly, however the conclusions synthesized by the author strike me as naive and I suspect that's also the conclusion of the majority. Whether it deserves an upvote is debateable. I downvoted.
4DanielVarga
I felt the confusion you are talking about. If readers could be expected to read the top-voted replies (RTFC), then the current distribution of votes would be ideal: The interesting article gets some well-deserved attention, and the skeptical replies give a counterbalance. But if readers don't read the comments, then frankly I think this article got too many upvotes when compared to many others. Offtopic: Is there a meta thread somewhere discussing the semantics of votes? I am happy that we don't use slashdot's baroque insightful/interesting/funny distinctions, but some consensus about the meaning of +1 would be nice.
3TheOtherDave
I don't know about a meta-thread, but the rule of thumb I've seen quoted often is "upvote what you want more of; downvote what you want less of." Karma scores are intended, on this view, as an indicator of how many people (net) want more entries like that. One implication of this view is that a score of 40 isn't "ten times better" than a score of 4, it just means that many more people want to see posts like this than don't want to. Of course, this view competes with people's entirely predictable tendency to treat karma as an indicator of the entry's (and the user's) overall worth, or as a game to maximize one's score on, or as a form of reward/punishment. Equally predictably, this predictable but unintended use of karma far far far outweighs the intended use.
0Will_Sawin
Karma-maximizing is often but not always a good approximation to worth-as-judged-by-community maximizing, which is a good thing to maximize.
0TheOtherDave
Yes. The question is how significant the gap between "often" and "always" is.
-1Will_Newsome
Though if you have a target audience in mind, it is sometimes worth posting things that will be downvoted by the community-at-large. (I've been doing this a lot recently, though I plan on cutting back and regaining some general rationalist credibility.)
0Kevin
The new meta-thread is due, feel free to make it. http://lesswrong.com/lw/1w4/fall_2010_meta_thread/
5FeepingCreature
The second reason is invalid unless the actor is self-deluding - a smart actor that faces being put out of work would silently adopt a SPR as his decision-making system without admitting to it. Since the superiority of SPR continues in many fields, either relevant actors are consistently not smart, performance is not a significant contributing criterion to their success, or they're self-deluding ie. overrating their own judgment as the poster stated. [edit] I'd guess a combination of the last two.
6Vladimir_M
Yes, I'd say it's a combination of the last two points, with emphasis on the second last. The critical question is whether maximizing the accuracy of your judgments is a practical way to get ahead in a given profession. Sometimes that is indeed the case, and in such fields we indeed see tremendous efforts to automate as much expert work as possible, often with great success, as in the electronics industry. But in professions that operate as more tightly-knit guilds, adherence to accepted standards is much more important than any objective metrics of effectiveness. Stepping outside of standard work procedures is often treated as a serious infraction with potentially severe consequences. (Especially if your non-standard methodology fails in some particular case, as it will sooner or later, and you can't cover your ass by claiming that you followed all the standard accepted procedures and having your profession back you up organizationally.) Now, you could try enhancing your work with decision models in secret. But even then, it's hard to do it in a completely secretive way, and moreover, human minds being what they are, most people can achieve professional success only if they are really sincerely convinced in their expertise and effectiveness. Keeping a public facade is hard for everyone except a very small minority of people.
4shokwave
I am not sure what you think the answers to these questions are, but I would say my personal opinion on the matter is that the more ideologically charged and legally dangerous a matter is, the more important accuracy and correctness - at the expense, if necessary, of strongly-held beliefs. I would also say that protecting the reputation of competency enjoyed by high-status people is not an activity that strongly correlates with being right; I predict a small negative correlation, in fact. Furthermore, there is a selection effect: learning the LW/OB folklore will result in you noticing specific cases of their application, and you are far, far more likely to write a post about that any about any given subject. That is, you see a prevalence of "standard bias explanation" because top-level posters are actively looking for actual cases of bias to discuss.

So why aren't SPRs in use everywhere? Probably, we deny or ignore the success of SPRs because of deep-seated cognitive biases, such as overconfidence in our own judgments. But if these SPRs work as well as or better than human judgments, shouldn't we use them?

Without even getting into the concrete details of these models, I'm surprised that nobody so far has pointed out the elephant in the room: in contemporary society, statistical inference about human behavior and characteristics is a topic bearing tremendous political, ideological, and legal weight. [*] Nowadays there exists a firm mainstream consensus that the use of certain sorts of conditional probabilities to make statistical predictions about people is discriminatory and therefore evil, and doing so may result not only in loss of reputation, but also in serious legal consequences. (Note that even if none of the forbidden criteria are built into your decision-making explicitly, that still doesn't leave you off the hook -- just search for "disparate impact" if you don't know what I'm talking about.)

Now of course, making any prediction about people at all necessarily involves one sort of statistical discriminatio... (read more)

If the best way to choose who to hire is with a statistical analysis of legally forbidden criteria, then keep your reasons secret and shred your work. Is that so hard?

6gwern
A loophole already closed: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Disparate_impact#The_80.25_rule
9Quirinus_Quirrell
That doesn't close the loophole, it adds a constraint. And it's only significant for those who both hire enough people to be vulnerable to statistical analysis of their hiring practices, and receive too many bad applicants from protected classes. If it is a significant constraint, you want to find that out from the data, not from guesswork, and apply the minimum legally acceptable correction factor. Besides, it's not like muggles are a protected class. And if they were? Just keep them from applying in the first place, by building your office somewhere they can't get to. There aren't any legal restrictions on that.

Besides, it's not like muggles are a protected class. And if they were? Just keep them from applying in the first place, by building your office somewhere they can't get to. There aren't any legal restrictions on that.

You joke, but the world [1] really is choking with inefficient, kludgey workarounds for the legal prohibition of effective employment screening. For example, the entire higher education market has become, basically, a case of employers passing off tests to universities that they can't legally administer themselves. You're a terrorist if you give an IQ test to applicants, but not if you require a completely irrelevant college degree that requires taking the SAT (or the military's ASVAB or whatever the call it now).

It feels so good to ban discrimination, as long as you don't have to directly face the tradeoff you're making.

[1] Per MattherW's correction, this should read "Western developed economies" instead of "the world" -- though I'm sure the phenomenon I've described is more general the form it takes in the West.

5MatthewW
You say 'the world', but it seems to me you're talking about a region which is a little smaller.
5GLaDOS
I'm not sure the correction is that relevant. The US and the EU together make up about 40% of global GDP (PPP). Several minor economies with nearly identical conditions and restrictions such as Canada, New Zealand, Australia, South Africa, Norway, Switzerland ... add up to another 3% or so.Most states in Latin America have similar legal prohibitions as well, they are not as well enforced, but avoiding them still imposes costs. This is mentioning nothing of Japan or other developed East Asian economies (though to be fair losses are probably much smaller than the developed West and perhaps even Latin America). The other half of the world's has a massive opportunity cost due to the mentioned half's described inefficiency. Converting this loss into number of lives or quality of life is a depressing exercise. Fortunately that is only a problem if you care about humans.
3MatthewW
Well, I'm in the UK, and there's no law against using IQ-style tests for job applicants here. Is that really the case in the US? (I assume the "You're a terrorist" bit was hyperbole.) Employers here still often ask for apparently-irrelevant degrees. But admission to university here isn't noticeably based on 'generic' tests like the SAT; it's mostly done on the grades from subject-specific exams. So I doubt employers are treating the degrees as a proxy for SAT-style testing.
5SilasBarta
Correction accepted.
6Strange7
You really are new here, aren't you? http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Americans_with_Disabilities_Act_of_1990#Title_III_-_Public_Accommodations_.28and_Commercial_Facilities.29 http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Zoning In short, there most certainly ARE legal restrictions on building your office somewhere deliberately selected for it's inaccessibility to those with a congenital inability to e.g. teleport, and a lack of teleportation-specific case law would not work in your favor, given the judge's access to statements you've already made.

In short, there most certainly ARE legal restrictions on building your office somewhere deliberately selected for it's inaccessibility to those with a congenital inability to e.g. teleport,

The Americans with Disabilities Act limits what you can build (every building needs ramps and elevators), not where you can build it. Zoning laws are blacklist-based, not whitelist-based, so extradimensional spaces are fine. More commonly, you can easily find office space in locations that poor people can't afford to live near. And in the unlikely event that race or national origin is the key factor, you get to choose which country or city's demographics you want.

A lack of teleportation-specific case law would not work in your favor, given the judge's access to statements you've already made.

This is the identity under which I speak freely and teach defense against the dark arts. This is not the identity under which I buy office buildings and hire minions. If it was, I wouldn't be talking about hiring strategies.

5[anonymous]
Up voted for having the sense to employ a blindingly obvious strategy that somehow consistently fails to become common sense.
0Strange7
But that they could, in principle, walk to and from.
6gwern
Yes, it does close the loophole. You say conceal the cause (intent to discriminate) and you can get away with as much effect (disproportionate exclusion) as you want. Except the law already specifies that the effect is punishable as well as the cause. So now the best you can do, assuming the populations are equally competent and suited for the job, is 20% discrimination. And of course, in the real world, populations usually differ in their suitability for the job. Blacks tend not to have as many CS degrees as whites, for example. So if you are an employer of CS degrees, you may not be able to get away with any discrimination before you have breached the 20% limit, and may need to discriminate against the non-blacks in order to be compliant. I would suspect that if the US Muggle legal system had anything to say about it, they would be. If magical-ness is conferred by genes, then it's violating either the general racial guideline or it's violating recent laws (signed by GWB, IIRC) forbidding employer discrimination based on genetics (in the context of genome sequencing, true, but probably general). If it's not conferred by genes, then there may be a general cultural basis on which to sue (Muggles as disabled because they lack an ability necessary for basic functioning in Wizarding society, perhaps).
3topynate
You can put degree requirements on the job advertisement, which should act as a filter on applications, something that can't be caught by the 80% rule. (Of course, universities tend to use racial criteria for admission in the US, something which, ironically, can be an incentive for companies to discriminate based on race even amongst applicants with CS degrees.)
2gwern
The 80% rule is only part of it. Again, racist requirements is an obvious loophole you should expect to have been addressed; you can only get away with a little covert discrimination if any. From http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Disparate_impact#Unintentional_discrimination : If you add unnecessary requirements as a stealth filter, how do you show the requirements are job-related?
1topynate
I thought we were talking about how to use necessary requirements without risking a suit, not how to conceal racial preferences by using cleverly chosen proxy requirements. But it looks like you can't use job application degree requirements without showing a business need either.
8Vladimir_M
topynate: The relevant landmark case in U.S. law is the 1971 Supreme Court decision in Griggs v. Duke Power Co. The court ruled that not just testing of prospective employees, but also academic degree requirements that have disparate impact across protected groups are illegal unless they are "demonstrably a reasonable measure of job performance." Now of course, "a reasonable measure of job performance" is a vague criterion, which depends on controversial facts as well as subjective opinion. To take only the most notable example, these people would probably say that IQ tests are a reasonable measure of performance for a great variety of jobs, but the present legal precedent disagrees. This situation has given rise to endless reams of of case law and a legal minefield that takes experts to navigate. At the end, as might be expected, what sorts of tests and academic requirements are permitted to different institutions in practice depends on arbitrary custom and the public perception of their status. The de facto rules are only partly codified formally. Thus, to take again the most notable example, the army and the universities are allowed to use what are IQ tests in all but name, which is an absolute taboo for almost any other institution.
2gwern
I wasn't. I was talking about how the obvious loopholes are already closed or have been heavily restricted (even at the cost of false positives), and hence how Quirrel's comments are naive and uninformed. Yes, that doesn't surprise me in the least.
6Barry_Cotter
My google-fu is not strong enough to find the legal doctrine, but in the US at least, you can be sued for ~implicit discrimination, i.e. if the newspaper you advertise in has a reader population that does not refelect the general population, you're discriminating against the under represented population.
6shokwave
...I thought this was a joke. Now... not so sure.
0Barry_Cotter
Disparate Impact
0Vladimir_M
See the last sentence of my first paragraph above (the one in parentheses).

An interesting story that I think I remember reading:

One study found that relatively inexperienced psychiatrists were more accurate at diagnosing mental illness than experienced ones. This is because inexperienced psychiatrists stuck closely to checklists rather than rely on their own judgment, and whether or not a diagnosis was considered "accurate" was based on how closely the reported symptoms matched the checklist. ;)

3Miller
If we are measuring the accuracy of A vs. B, we are implicitly measuring A against gold standard C, and B against gold standard C. If a better C is not readily available, we may choose to use A or B as an approximation, the choice of which determines our outcome. Now I wonder: Are the people that are sympathetic to the hypothesis that computers are better in the cases above (and ignored because of biases) assuming we made the fallacy of using humans as a gold standard? Are the people that are sympathetic to the hypothesis that humans are better (and ignored because of biases) assuming we made the fallacy of using computers as a gold standard? The union of which is a lot of upvotes. I can't decide which was meant.
1Miller
This is one of the top 3 rated comments on this post. I think you should specify more directly how this anecdote relates to how you interpret the article's intention.
2prase
He should specify where he has read that.
0CronoDAS
I don't remember. I may have actually heard one of my parents talking about it instead of reading it. So consider it an urban legend.

If this is not amazing enough, consider the fact that even when experts are given the results of SPRs, they still can't outperform those SPRs (Leli & Filskov 1985; Goldberg 1968).

Now THAT part is just plain embarrassing. I mean, it's truly a mark of shame upon us if we have a tool that we know works, we are given access to the tool, and we still can't do better than the tool itself, unaided. (EDIT: By "we", I mean "the experts in the relevant fields"... which I guess isn't really a "we" as such, but you know what I mean)

Anyways, are there any nice online indexes or whatever of SPRs that make it easy to put in class of problem and have it find a SPR that's been verified to work for that sort of problem?

4SilasBarta
Coincidentally, I was planning to write an article "defending" the use of fallacies on Bayesian grounds. A typical passage would go like this: Well, it seems we actually do live in such a world, where (some classes of) experts make predictable errors, and don't take trivial steps to make their opinions more accurate (and entangled with the subject matter).
2Psy-Kosh
Well, experts still do better than non-experts on average (afaik), just that they seem to totally ignore tools that could let them do a whole lot better, and also apparently can't do much better than the tools themselves, even when they're able to use the tools.
0JoshuaZ
Making predictable errors isn't the same thing as their opinions being anti-correlated with reality.

If anybody would like to try some statistical machine learning at home, it's actually not that hard. The tough part is getting a data set. Once that's done, most of the examples in this article are things you could just feed to some software like Weka, press a few buttons, and get a statistical model. BAM!

Let's try an example. Here is some breast cancer diagnostic data, showing a bunch of observations of people with breast cancer (age, size of tumors, etc.) and whether or not the cancer reoccurred after treatment. Can we predict cancer recurrence?

If you look at it with a decision tree, it turns out that you can get about 70% accuracy by observing two of the several factors that were observed, in a very simple decision procedure. You can do a little better by using something more sophisticated, like a naive Bayes classifier. These show us what factors are the most important, and how.

If you're interested, go ahead and play around. It's pretty easy to get started. Obviously, take everything with a grain of salt, but still, basic machine learning is surprisingly easy.

I second the advice.

Let me brag a bit. Once in a friendly discussion the following question came up: How to predict for an unknown first name whether it is a male or female name. This was in a context of Hungarian names, as all of us were Hungarians. I had a list of Hungarian first names in digital format. The discussion turned into a bet: I said I can write a program in half an hour that tells with at least 70% precision the sex of a first name it never saw before. I am quite fast with writing small scripts. It wasn't even close: It took me 9 minutes to

  • split my sets of 1000 male and 1000 female names into a random 1000-1000 train-test split,
  • split each name into character 1,2- and 3-grams. E.g.: Luca was turned into ^L u c a$ ^Lu uc ca$ ^Luc uca$.
  • feed the training data into a command line tool to train a maxent model,
  • test the accuracy of the model on the unseen test data.

The model reached an accuracy of 90%. In retrospect, this is not surprising at all. Looking into the linear model, the most important feature it identified was whether the name ends with an 'a'. This trivial model alone reaches some 80% precision for Hungarian names, so if I knew this in advance, I could have won the bet in 30 seconds instead of 9 minutes, with the sed command s/a$/a FEMALE/.

3matt
These sound like powers I should acquire. Could you drop some further hints on: * "a command line tool to train a maxent model" * how you tested the accuracy of the model (tools that let you do that in the remaining minutes, rather than general principles)
4DanielVarga
I used Zhang Le's tool. Note that it is a rather obscure thing, not an industry standard like say, the huge Weka and Mallet packages. It made very easy the tasks you ask for. When I had a train and test data featurized, built the model and told me its accuracy on the test data.

Are some SPRs easy to exploit?

5shokwave
Depends on what you're measuring. I can't see how it would be exploitable for things like predicting wine quality (actually greenhousing your grapes to control temperature and rainfall might just make them better) but definitely a specific SPR for, say, rating dossiers for hiring would be exploitable if you knew or could guess at which cues it's using.

SPR's sound a lot like the Outside View.

5lukeprog
Oh yes. Added. 'Outside view', I believe, is a term of Kahneman's, and is used in the literature by lots of these people who work on SPRs, for example Dawes. Kahneman begins his Edge.org master class on thinking by discussing the outside view.
3shokwave
SPRs sound like a method to ensure a very accurate outside view.
[-]SK290

This is a great article, but it only lists studies where SPRs have succeeded. In fairness, it would be good to know if there were any studies that showed SPRs failing (and also consider publication bias, etc.).

1lukeprog
Definitely.
0Miller
My principle problem with this article is that you appear to promote the idea that these SPRs are being ignored for extremely bad reasons, rather than they were ignored for decent reasons. So when you say 'definitely' here I have a problem that you are compartmentalizing the arguments and not admitting the problems with your post. Also, I don't think this is a great article and in proportion to it getting +40 votes I have a poor opinion of this community (or at least it's karma system where 0 should be neutral). edit: My last paragraph here is excessively dramatic and I retract it.
1lukeprog
Miller, Does this look like "not admitting the problems with [my] post"?
0Miller
It would be more constructive of me if I actually helped find counter-evidence, rather than whinging about your not doing so. I think you've put a lot of effort into updating your position.

Does SPR beat prediction markets?

4sketerpot
If it did, then you could make a lot of money on a prediction market with enough cash in it. This would cause the market to give better answers.

Well, SPRs can plausibly outperform average expertise. That's because most of the expertise is utter and complete sham.

The recidivism in example...

The judges, or psychologists, or the like, what in the world makes them experts on predicting the criminals? Did they read an unbiased sample of recidivism? Did they do any practice, earning marks for predicting criminals? Anything?

Resounding no. They never in their lives did anything that should have earned them the expert status on this task. They did other stuff that puts them first on the list when you're l... (read more)

I have two concerns about the practical implementation of this sort of thing:

  1. It seems like there are cases where if a rule is being used then people could abuse it. For example, in job applications or admissions to medical schools. A better understanding of how the rule relates to what it predicts would be needed.

If X+Y predicts Z does that mean enhancing X and Y will up the probability of Z? Not necessarily, consider the example of happy marriages. Will having more sex make your relationship happier? Or does the rule work because happy couples tend to... (read more)

9shokwave
Obviously, yes.
6TheOtherDave
It probably depends somewhat on with whom you are having it.
1shokwave
True. One of my nodes for "relationship" is consensual; most definitely in that case it would make the relationship much less happy.
3DSimon
Well, unless the quality of the sex is causally linked to the quantity, such that having lots and lots of sex (past a certain threshold) makes each individual session disproportionately worse. This is true for a lot of people's libidos. To put it another way: it's not the frequency of the motion in the ocean, but the amplitude of the waves.
5shokwave
But probably not true for the quantity of sex in almost all relationships, I would bet.
1datadataeverywhere
Although I agree with you, I feel like I should point out that it is somewhat nonsensical for most relationships to be sub-optimal in this way. If both parties want to have more sex, and they can (otherwise the question wouldn't really be valid), but they don't, that's a little weird, don't you think? We can talk about optimizing for other things (e.g. careers), but I don't think that's really the issue, since many couples, when explicitly told that they would be happier if they had more sex, just start having more sex, without sacrificing anything that they end up wanting back.

Although I agree with you, I feel like I should point out that it is somewhat nonsensical for most relationships to be sub-optimal in this way. If both parties want to have more sex, and they can (otherwise the question wouldn't really be valid), but they don't, that's a little weird, don't you think?

Weird certainly but this is a kind of weirdness that humans are notorious for. We are terrible happiness optimisers. In the case of sex specifically having more of it is not as simple as walking over to the bedroom. For males and females alike you can want to be having more sex, be aware that having more sex would benefit your relationship and still not be 'in the mood' for it. A more indirect approach to the problem of libido and desire is required - the sort of thing that humans are not naturally good at optimising.

1datadataeverywhere
I agree on every point. I also think part of this is simply that shared knowledge that is not common knowledge (until acknowledged between parties) is much more difficult to act upon. I think that "okay, we're going to have sex now, because it will make us happier" is a little like "okay, I'm going to the gym now, because it will make me feel better", which may be the same thing you meant about being "in the mood", but I think it's even harder for sex, because we are perhaps less willing to see sex except as immediate gratification.
3NancyLebovitz
I've heard more than once that having more sex on a schedule in the hopes of having children is a miserable experience for couples with fertility problems. I don't know whether having more sex in the hopes of being happier (rather than because the people involved want sex more for the fun of it) could have similar side effects.
1Blueberry
It's fairly common for sex therapists to recommend that couples schedule sex and have sex at all (but not only) scheduled times, on the grounds that people may not be in the mood at first, but enjoy it anyway. While it may be a miserable experience for a few people, I doubt that it is miserable in general (and I'm not sure why it would be).
1NancyLebovitz
It's certainly possible for people to have akrasia in regards to pleasure, and scheduling can help with that. I think possible problems come in if a partner (possibly both partners in the case of fertility) really doesn't want to at the moment, but is feeling pressured.
7MatthewW
Yes, several of these models look like they're likely to run into trouble of the Goodhart's law type ("Any observed statistical regularity will tend to collapse once pressure is placed upon it for control purposes").
3cousin_it
I think it's safe to say that having less sex will make the relationship less happy, so there is some causality involved.
-2AstroCJ
What? Are you from the mythical land where every partnering has the same intensity of sex drive?
1wedrifid
Yes. Almost certainly. But there are plenty of other examples you could pick from where there is not causality involved (and some for which causality is negative).
-4BillyOblivion
[quote]Will having more sex make your relationship happier? [/quote] Having more sex will make ME happier. If my wife finds out though...

While this is promising indeed, it is wise not to forget about Optimization By Proxy that can occur when the thing being optimised is (or is under the control of) an intelligent agent.

My gut reaction is that this doesn't demonstrate that SPRs are good, just that humans are bad. There are tons of statistical modeling algorithms that are more sophisticated than SPRs.

Unless, of course, SPR is another word for "any statistical modeling algorithm", in which case this is just the claim that statistical machine learning is a good approach, which anyone as Bayesian as the average LessWronger probably agrees with.

8shokwave
Not in and of itself a good thing. As demonstrated recently sophisticated statistics can suffice simply to allow one to confuse oneself in a sophisticated knot - that's harder to untie. There is a case to be made for promoting the simplest algorithm that outperforms current methods, and SPRs seem to fit this bill. As for what SPR stands for, the post makes it pretty clear that they are a class of rules that predict a (desired) property using weighted cues (observable properties). I am not familiar enough with statistical modelling to say if that is a shared goal among all algorithms.
2jsteinhardt
The post gives an example of an SPR that uses weighted cues. But he specifically says indicating that there are other types of SPRs, and I currently have no idea what those other types might be. I agree with you that complicated statistical tests can lead to spurious results; simple statistical tests can also lead to spurious results if the person using them doesn't understand them. I naievely associate both of these with "the test was designed to correct against a different type of flaw in experimental design than actually occurred". When the focus of the statistical test is on accurately modeling a given situation, I think it is less difficult to realize when a model choice makes sense and when it doesn't, so more sophisticated approaches will probably do better, since they come closer to carving reality at its joints. This might be an inferential distance error on my part, though, since I have training in this area, so errors that I personally can avoid might not be generally avoidable.
0shokwave
I agree with you for smart people; I do see a lot of value, though, in idiot-proof statistics. Weighted-cue SPRs are almost too simple to screw up.
0jsteinhardt
Also, while this isn't super-relevant, given that I already agree with your claim about people confusing themselves, my impression is that the link you gave presents moderate-to-weak evidence against this. I didn't read the entire article that was linked to discussing the statistical analysis (if there's a particular section you think I should read, please let me know), but my understanding was that in some sense the "experimental procedure" was the issue, not the statistics. In other words, Bem considered potentially hundreds of hypotheses about his data, but only reported on a few, so that p-values of 0.02 are not super-impressive (since out of 100 hypotheses we would expect a few to hit that by chance). Bem's experiments all basically ask "is this coin biased", which isn't a very complicated question to answer. It is the sophisticated statistics that corrects for the flawed procedure.
0shokwave
It wasn't a very good example at all. I basically grepped my memory for "idiot statistics" and that one featured strongly. The problem there was not a misuse of statistical tests, it was a misinterpretation of the significance of statistical tests.

Besides the legal issues with discrimination and disparate impact, another important issue here is that jobs that involve making decisions about people tend to be high-status. As a very general tendency, the higher-status a profession is, the more its practitioners are likely to organize in a guild-like way and resist intrusive innovations by outsiders -- especially innovations involving performance metrics that show the current standards of the profession in a bad light, or even worse, those that threaten a change in the way their work is done that might ... (read more)

Sometimes, being rational is easy. When there exists a reliable statistical prediction rule for the problem you're considering, you need not waste your brain power trying to make a careful judgment.

Unfortunately linear models for a lot of situations are simply not available. The dozen or so ones in the literature are the exception, not the rule.

0matt
And those that exist are not always easy to find. And those that are found are not always easy to use in industry (where sophisticated computer skills are often the things the marketing grad taught erself to do in Excel).
[-][anonymous]60

Correct me if I'm wrong, but the SPR is just a linear model, right? Statistics is an under appreciated field in many walks of life. My own field of speciality, experimental design, is treated with down right suspicion by scientists who have not encountered it before, who find the results counter-intuitive (when they have 4 controllable variables in an experiment they want to vary them one at a time, while the best way is to vary all 4 simultaneously...)

2Nominull
I also find that counter-intuitive, is there a short explanation of why?
2Sly
I am curious: could you explain why it is better to vary all 4?
9[anonymous]
Briefly: because to do so assumes that they do not interact, and if they DO interact, you will have gathered no information on said interactions.
1CronoDAS
That makes sense... if your inputs are X and Y, and you want to figure out what your output f(X,Y) is, it seems like you'll eventually have to vary X and Y simultaneously in order to tell the difference between f(X,Y) = aXY + c and f(X,Y) = aX + bY + c.
5[anonymous]
quite, although usually you'll have a model f(x,y)=aXY+bX+cY+d. I'm actually underselling this approach, because if I had two variables X, and Y which can be observed between (-1,1), and only have two observations to do it in then we're much better going (X,Y)=(-1,1) and (1,-1) rather than (0,1),(1,0), because we're gathering more information. We always want to design in the location with the most variance, because thats the hardest place to predict. Given that the model we're looking at is linear in both the parameters and the variables then we know the places where we get the most variation will be at the extremes. Obviously we have no information if we think there might be some kind of quadratic terms here, but one of the nice things about design for linear models is you can build your experimentation to iteratively build up information. Typically in an industrial setting we'll have a few dozen different factors which we think might affect our outcome, so we can design to eliminate down to a handful by using a very basic linear model in a screening experiment, then use a more sophisticated design called a central composite design. Now if we want a mechanistic model, something based on what we know on the physics of the situation (say we have some differential equations describing the reaction), then designing becomes harder, which is where my research is.

You speak of incredible success without given a success rate of the models. The fact that there are a dozen cases where specific models outperformed human reasoning doesn't prove much.

At the moment you recommend other people to use SPRs for their decision making based on "expert judgment". How about providing us a SPR that tells us for which problems we should use SPRs?

SPRs can be gamed much more directly than human experts. For example, imagine an SPR in place of all hiring managers. In our current place, with hiring managers, we can guess at what goes in to their decisionmaking and attempt to optimize for it, but because each manager is somewhat different, we can't know that well. A single SPR that took over for all the managers, or even a couple of very popular ones, would strongly encourage applicants to optimize for the variable most weighted in the equation. Over time this would likely decrease the value of the SPR... (read more)

3Barry_Cotter
Goodhart's Law W1(Quantitative skills) + W2(Written and Oral Communication Skills) + W3(Ability to work with loose supervision) + W4(Domain Expertise) + W5(Social Skills) + W6(Prestige Markers) No, but I imagine that taking a grab basket of plausible correlates of the desired trait and throwing them into a regression function would be a good first draft. Then iterate.

Hi Luke,

Great post. Will be writing something about the legal uses of SPRs in the near future.

Anyway, the link to the Grove and Meehl study doesn't seem to work for me. It says the file is damaged and cannot be repaired.

3Douglas_Knight
The copy on Meehl's posthumous website works for me. I found it with google scholar.
1JohnD
Ah yes, that seems to work. Thanks
1lukeprog
Fixed, thanks.

The thing that makes me twitch about SPRs is a concern that they won't change when the underlying conditions which created their data sets change. This doesn't mean that humans are good at noticing that sort of thing, either. However, it's at least worth thinking about which approach is likely to overshoot worse when something surprising happens. Or whether there's some reason to think that the greater usual accuracy of SPRs leads to enough bigger reserves that the occasional overshoot problem (if such are worse than in a non-SPR system) is compensated for.

On interviews, I had a great deal of success hiring for clerical assistant positions by simply getting the interviewees to do a simple problem in front of us. It turned out to be a great, reliable and easy-to-justify sorter of candidates.

But, of course, it was neither unstructured nor much of an "interview" as such.

1shokwave
Again, test not interview. Their GPA is an average measure of maybe thousands of such simple problems - probably on average more rigorously produced, presented, and corrected than your problem presented in the interview. Deciding based on a test in person instead of deciding on a number that represents thousands of such individual tests smacks of anecdotal decision-making.
4eshear
Unfortunately, GPAs can lie. You cannot be certain of the quality of the problems and evaluation that was averaged to produce the GPA. So running your own test of known difficulty works well to verify what you see on the resume. For example, I have to hire programmers. We give all incoming programmers a few relatively easy programming problems as part of the interview process because we've found that no matter what the resume says, it's possible that they actually do not know how to program. Good resume + good interview result is a much stronger indicator than good resume alone.
0tenshiko
A significant problem is the weighting of certain courses, particularly Advanced Placement ones. A GPA of 3.7, seeming quite respectable to the unaware, can be obtained by work of quality 83%, and that's assuming the class didn't offer extra credit.
0Wandering_Sophist
I don't think he is likely to hire programmers straight out of high school. Giving IB/AP/Honors classes extra weight in high school is necessary to offset the additionally difficulty of these classes. Otherwise, high school students would have a direct disincentive to take advanced classes.
0[anonymous]
A swift googling brings up this forthcoming study of about 900 high schools in Texas:
0tenshiko
But there's still the additional incentive of prestige and signalling, isn't there? That should be enough for the serious scholar. It's a significant problem when non-AP-labelled courses are often passed over for the purpose of a cheap grade boost.
3Dmytry
Since when did greater rigour and averaging of more problems imply greater degree of correlation with performance at one specific job? I call halo effect here. Greater rigour, bigger number, more accurate, more corrected, all combined really 'good' qualities about the GPA value spill over into your feeling of how well it'll correlate with performance at specific job, versus a 'bad' ill measured value. Truth is, say, ill measured hand size based on eyeballing can easily correlate better with measured finger length, than body weight measured using ultra high precision scientific scales with accuracy of a milligram (microgram, nanogram, whatever). Just because hammer is a tool you build things with, and butter knife is a kitchen utensil, doesn't make hammer better than butter knife as a screw driver.
0shokwave
Well, actually... But more on point, you'd need to justify that the test you give is more correlated than GPA with performance - this is why I support simple programming tests (because they demonstrably are more correlated than academic indicators) but for a 'clerical assistant' position as described above, a specific test doesn't immediately spring to mind, and so it's suspect.
1Dmytry
You aren't looking for 'correlation' usually, you're looking for screening out the serial job applicant who can't do the job they're applying for (and keeps re-applying to many places)... just ask 'em to do some work similar to what they will be doing as per LorenzofromOz method, and you'll at least be assured they can do work. While with GPA you won't be assured of anything what so ever. For the programming, the simplest dumbest check works to screen out those entirely incapable, when screening by PhD would not. http://www.codinghorror.com/blog/2007/02/why-cant-programmers-program.html PhD might correlate better with performance than fizzbuzz does (the latter being a binary test of extremely basic knowledge), but PhD does not screen out those who will just waste your time, and fizzbuzz (your personal variation of it) does.
0A1987dM
Holy crap... I think I had read about the FizzBuzz thing a while ago, but I didn't remember about the 199 in 200 thing... Would it be possible to sue the institutions issuing those PhD or something? :-)
1Dmytry
Well, I don't know what % of the CS-related PhDs can't do FizzBuzz, maybe the percentage is rather small. (Also, sue for what? You are not their client. The incapable dude that was given a degree, that's their client. Your over-valuation of this degree as evidence of capability is your own problem) The issue is that, as Joel explains, the job applicants are a sample extremely biased towards incompetence: http://www.joelonsoftware.com/items/2005/01/27.html [Though I would think that the incompetents with degrees would be more able to find incompetent employer to work at. And PhDs should be able to find a company that hires PhDs for signalling reasons] The issue with the hiring methods here, is that we easily confuse "more accurate measurement of X" with "stronger correlation to Y", and "stronger correlation to Y" with hiring better staff (the one that doesn't sink your company), usually out of some dramatically different population than the one on which correlation was found. Furthermore, a 'correlation' is such an inexact measure of how test relates to performance. Comparing correlations is like comparing apples to oranges by weight. The 'fizzbuzz' style problems measure performance near the absolute floor level, but with very high reliability. Virtually no-one who fails fizzbuzz is a good hire. Virtually no-one who passes fizzbuzz (an unique fizzbuzz, not the popular one) is completely incapable of programming. The degrees correlate to performance at the higher level, but with very low reliability - there are brilliant people with degrees, there are complete incompetents with degrees, there's brilliant people and incompetents without degrees. edit: other example: http://blog.rethinkdb.com/will-the-real-programmers-please-stand-up Reversing a linked list is a good one unless the candidate knows how to. See, the issue is that educational institutions don't teach how to think up a way to reverse linked list. Nor do they test for that. They might teach how to r

The post mentions the experts using the results of the SPR. What happens if you reverse it, and give the SPR the prediction of the expert?

4lukeprog
That's called a 'bootstrapped' SPR. It's one way of building an SPR. And yes, in many cases the SPR ends up being reliably better than the expert judgments that were used to build it.
2DanielLC
I was wondering more how much better it is than a normal SPR. Also, I wonder what weight it would give to the expert.

Cosma Shalizi has a nice bibliography here

60 years of research

I would like to emphasize this part. It's not just scattered papers back then. Meehl wrote a book surveying the field in 1955.

AI systems can generally whoop humans when a limited feature set can be discovered that covers the span of a large class of examples to good effect. The challenge is when you seemingly need a new feature for each new example in order to differentiate it from the rest of the examples in that class. Essentially you are saying that the problem can be mapped to a simple function. Some problems can.

Let's imagine we are classifying avian vs. reptile. Our first example might be a gecko, and we might say 'well it's green'. So 'Color is Green' is a clue\feature a... (read more)

3shokwave
A fair point and good caution against turning SPRs into your hammer for every nail, but irrelevant in the case lukeprog is discussing; we already have the expert system, we already know it works better than the experts, we just aren't using it.
1Miller
Irrelevant is excessive. When you say 'system A works better than system B' this implies that system A should be used and this is clear cut. But the notion 'works better' lacks a rigorous definition. Is the machine better if it wins 90% of the time by 5%, and fails the other 10% by 40%? It's not as simple as saying .9 .05 > .1 .4. The cost of error isn't necessarily linear. Now why these systems aren't used in ensembles with humans is indeed a great question. I can imagine that in most cases we could also ask 'why don't we double the number of experts who are collaborating on a given problem?' under the presumption that more minds would likely result in a better performance across the board. I wouldn't be surprised if there was a lot of overlap in the answers. Coordination difficulty is likely high up there. Thus, possibly becomes the explanation.
9Vaniver
What? These are generally binary decisions, with a known cost to false positives and false negatives, and known rates of false positives and false negatives. It should be be trivial to go from that to a utility-valued error score.
1Miller
You just presumed away my argument. I claim specifically that the relationship between various classes of errors is not well-defined. This can lead to abuse of the term 'better'. Please tell me why I should take that as a presumption.
0shokwave
Because those are the class of problems this post discusses. From the top of the post:
2kybernetikos
I think this is the kind of question that Miller is talking about. Just because a system is correct more often, doesn't necessarily mean it's better. For example if the human experts allowed more people out who went on to commit relatively minor violent offences and the SPRs do this less often, but are more likely to release prisoners who go on to commit murder then there would be legitimate discussion over whether the SPR is actually better. I think this is exactly what he is talking about when he says Whether or not there is evidence that says this is a real effect I don't know, but to address it what you really need to measure is total utility of outcomes rather than accuracy.
0Miller
Yes. You got it, exactly.
-2Miller
No. I'm talking about classes of errors. As in, which is better? * A test that reports 100 false positives for every 100 false negatives for disease X * A test that reports 110 false positives for every 90 false negatives for disease X The cost of fp vs. fn is not defined automatically. If humans are closer to #1 than #2, and I develop a system like #2, I might define #2 to be better. Then later on down the line I stop talking about how I defined better, and I just use the word better, and no one questions it because hey... better is better, right?
3shokwave
Which is more costly, false positives or false negatives? This is an easy question to answer. If false positives, #1 is better. If false negatives, #2. I really do not see what your point is. These problems you bring up are easily solved.
6handoflixue
Which is better: Releasing a violent prisoner, or keeping a harmless one incarcerated? If you can find an answer that 90% of the population agrees on, then I think you've done better than every politician in history. That people do NOT agree suggest to me that it's hardly a trivial question...
0shokwave
How violent, how preventably violent, how harmless, how incarcerated, how long incarcerated? For any specific case with these agreed-upon, I am confident a supermajority would agree. That people don't agree suggests one side is comparing releasing a serial killer to incarcerating a drifter in jail a short while, and the other side is comparing releasing a middle-aged man who in a fit of passion struck his adulterous wife to incarcerating Ghandi for the term of his natural life. More generally, they are deciding based on one specific example they have strongly available to them. In the state you phrased it, that question is about as answerable as "how long is a piece of string?".
0Miller
Yes. Thank you. Since at least one person understood me, I'm gonna jump off the merry-go-round at this point.
0handoflixue
(For reference, I realize an expert runs in to the same issue, I just think it's unfair to say that the issue is "easily solved")
2jimrandomh
Many tests have a continuous, adjustable parameter for sensitivity, letting you set the trade-off however you want. In that case, we can refrain from judging the relative badness of false positives and false negatives, and use ROCA, which is basically the integral over all such trade-offs. Tests that are going to be combined into a larger predictor are usually measured this way. Machine learning packages generally let you specify a "cost matrix", which is the cost of each possible confusion. For a 2-valued test, it would be a 2x2 matrix with zeroes on the diagonal, and the cost of A->B and B->A errors in the other two spots. For a test with N possible results, the matrix is NxN, with zeroes on the diagonals, and each (row,col) position is the cost of a mistake that confuses the result corresponding to that row with the result corresponding to that column.
2shokwave
Keep in mind this is in the conclusion of lukeprog's post: Now, If the cost of error isn't linear, determine what function it follows, then use that function instead of a linear function to compare the relative costs, which will tell you which works better. I stand by it. The post is saying, given that SPRs work, work better than experts, and don't fail where experts don't, we should use them instead of experts. Your points were that SPRs don't always work, tend not to work in border cases, and might fail in dangerous cases. The first point is only true in cases this post is not concerned with, the second is equally true of experts and SPRs, and the third is also equally true of experts and SPRs.

Also, there is an article by Dawes, Faust and Meehl. Despite the fact it was published 7 years prior to House of Cards, it contains some information not described in the chapter 3 of House of Cards.

For example, the awesome result by Goldberg: linear models of human judges were more accurate than human judges themselves:

in cases of disagreement, the models were more often correct than the very judges on whom they were based.

I think the reason I don't use statistics more often is the difficulty of getting good data sets; and even when there is good data, there are often ethical problems with following it. For example: Bob lives in America, and is seeking to maximize his happiness. Americans who report high levels of spiritual conviction are twice as likely to report being "very happy" than the least religious. Should he become a devout Christian? There's evidence that the happiness comes from holding the majority opinion; should he then strive to believe whatever ... (read more)

6IlyaShpitser
Bob should not become a Christian to become happier for the same reason that he should not stay away from hospitals if he's sick (after all, sick people are a lot more likely to be in a hospital).

People looking for additional resources on this matter should know that such linear models are often called "multi attribute utility models" (MAUT), and that they're discussed extensively in the literature of decision analysis and multi-criteria decision making. They're also used in choice models in the science of marketing.

The word "statistical" in the name used here is a bit of a red herring.

Atlantic, The Brain on Trial:

In the past, researchers have asked psychiatrists and parole-board members how likely specific sex offenders were to relapse when let out of prison. Both groups had experience with sex offenders, so predicting who was going straight and who was coming back seemed simple. But surprisingly, the expert guesses showed almost no correlation with the actual outcomes. The psychiatrists and parole-board members had only slightly better predictive accuracy than coin-flippers. This astounded the legal community.

So researchers tried a m

... (read more)

Update: Added about 10 more direct PDF links to the original article.

3paul_watcher
Thank you for this article. Some people may react to finding that their professional opinion be less accurate than a simple formula, but I get excited instead. It's such a great opportunity to become more accurate, with such comparatively little effort! I'm particularly interested in the medical SPRs; I aim to be a doctor, and if these will help me be better than the average doctor in many cases, then so be it. I suspect that I'll have to use them secretly.

Other related reading that I don't think has been mentioned yet:

Ian Ayres (cofounder of stickK.com) has a popular book called Super Crunchers that argues this exact thesis. http://www.amazon.com/Super-Crunchers-Thinking-Numbers-Smart/dp/0553805401

A classic is Tetlock's Expert Political Judgment. http://press.princeton.edu/titles/7959.html

[-][anonymous]10

I cannot help unleashing an evil laugh whenever I discover another tool to aid in world domination. Thank you.

Another example of this: the US political models did fantastic in predicting all sorts of outcomes on election day 2012, far exceeding all sorts of pundits or people adjusting the numbers based on gut feelings and assumptions, despite often being pretty simple or tantamount to poll averaging.

Just felt like saying thank you to lukeprog and all those who commented; this has been a great help to me in deciding what to read about next regarding determination of guaranteed values for the service the department I work in performs.

Humans use more complex utility functions to evaluate something like martial happiness. If you train a statistical model on a straight numeric value for martial happiness than the model only optimizes towards that specific aspect of happiness.

A good evaluation should test the model that trained on hedonistic happiness rating on something like the likelihood of divorce.

2wnoise
I think you mean "marital" here. (Despite the similarities, love is not a battlefield.)
0ChristianKl
Okay, English isn't my first language.
2komponisto
You could easily have made the same typo even if it were; we're talking about the mere transposition of two adjacent letters. (Another example: "casual" vs. "causal", which often trips me up in reading.)
2A1987dM
In Italian that's even worse, since causale does mean ‘causal’ but casuale means ‘random’.
0SilasBarta
Cool, that means you would get the joke about how "women are interested in causal sex"!
9ata
Is there acausal sex? (Would that be, like, having (phone/cyber)sex with someone in a different Tegmark universe via some form of communication built on UDT acausal trade?)

Acausal sexual reproduction is quite plausible, in a sense. Suppose you were a single woman living in a society with access to sophisticated genetic engineering, and you wanted to give birth to a child that was biologically yours and not do any unnatural optimizing. You could envision your ideal mate in detail, reverse-engineer the genetics of this man, and then create a sperm population that the man could have produced had he existed. I can easily imagine a genetic engineer offering this service: you walk into the office, describe the man's physical attributes, personality, and even life history, and the engineer does the rest as much as is possible (in this society, we know that a plurality of men who played shortstop in Little League have a certain allele, etc.) The child could grow up and meaningfully learn things about the counterfactual father--if you learned that the father was prone to depression, that would mean that you should watch out for that as well.

If the mother really wants to, she can take things further and specify that the man should be the kind of person who would have, had he existed, gone through the analogous procedure (with a surrogate or artificial womb), and that the counterfactual woman he would have specified would have been her. In this case, we can say that the man and the woman have acausally reproduced.

Hmm. So the man has managed to "acausally reproduce", fulfill his utility function, in spite of not existing. You could go further and posit an imaginary couple who would have chosen each other for the procedure - so they succeed in "acausally reproducing", even though neither of them exists. Then when someone tries to write a story about the imaginary couple, the child becomes observable to the writer and starts doing some reproducing of her own :-)

5Desrtopa
My interpretation of acausal sexual reproduction would be something more like All You Zombies.
3Vaniver
What makes this acausal? That is, when are future inputs modifying present results? Or are you using a different definition of acausal?
3HonoreDB
I meant it in the sense of ata's parent comment, although there is a backwards arrow in there: the phenotype is determining the genotype rather than vice versa.
[-]gwern120

You simply must read http://commonsenseatheism.com/wp-content/uploads/2010/10/Sinhababu-Possible-Girls.pdf - possibly the most romantic paper I've ever read.

2wedrifid
That paper is absolutely brilliant! I kept laughing every time a new clearly logically reasoned yet humorous detail was explored.
5wedrifid
If you're basing the sex on acausal trade then you should perhaps refer to it as acausal prostitution. Or possibly acausal marriage.
1andrew sauer
You might not even need to go to a different Tegmark universe lol, given that multiple people have independently come up with this idea
0MugaSofer
* Simulate agent. * Check if it tries to do the same for you. * If it does, build it a body and have sex. * In a galaxy far far away, an agent simulates you, sees you try to do the same for them. * It clones you and has sex. Does this fit the bill?
0David_Gerard
Acausal conception. (Acausal contraception.)

It's interesting to me that the proper linear model example is essentially a stripped down version of a very simple neural network with a linear activation function.

1gwern
Is that really true? Couldn't one say that of just about any Turing-complete (or less) model of computation? 'Oh, it's interesting that they are really just a simple unary fixed-length lambda-calculus function with constant-value parameters.' 'Oh, it's interesting that they are really just restricted petri-nets with bounded branching factors.' 'Oh, it's interesting that these are modelable by finite automata.' etc. (Plausible-sounding gobbledygook included to make the point.)
2mistercow
Yes, sort of, but a) a linear classifier is not a Turing-complete model of computation, and b) there is a clear resemblance that can be seen by merely glancing at the equations.
0Will_Sawin
I would argue that neurons, neural nets, SPRs, and everyone else doing linear regression use those techniques because it's the simplest way to aggregate data.
[-][anonymous]00

I'm skeptical, and will now proceed to question some of the assertions made/references cited. Note that I'm not trained in statistics.

Unfortunately, most of the articles cited are not easily available. I would have liked to check the methodology of a few more of them.

|For example, one SPR developed in 1995 predicts the price of mature Bordeaux red wines at auction better than expert wine tasters do.

The paper doesn't actually establish what you say it does. There is no statistical analysis of expert wine tasters, only one or two anecdotal statements of the... (read more)

I was thinking of writing a post about Bishop & Trout when I didn't see it mentioned on this site before, but I'm glad you beat me to it. (Among other things, I lent out my copy and so would have difficulty writing up a review). It's a great book.

Your upload of Dawes's "The Robust Beauty of Improper Linear Models in Decision Making" seems to be broken- at least, I'm not able to access it.

0shokwave
Neither.
0lukeprog
Dang. Fixed.

Wow. I highly recommend reading the Dawes pdf, it's illuminating:

Expert doctors coded [variables from] biopsies of patients with Hodgkin's disease and then made an overall rating of the severity of the process. The overall rating did not predict the survival time of the 193 patients, all of whom died. (The correlations of survival time with ratings was virtually 0, some in the wrong direction). The variables that the doctors coded, however, did predict survival time when they were used in a multiple regression model.

In summary, proper linear models work for a very simple reason. People are good at picking out the right predictor variables ... People are bad at integrating information from diverse and incomparable sources. Proper linear models are good at such integration ...

He then goes on to show that improper linear models still beat human judgment. If your reaction to the top-level post wasn't endorsement of statistical methods for these problems, this pdf is a bunch more evidence that you can use to update your beliefs about statistical methods of prediction.

9TheOtherDave
That is a beautiful summary sentence, incidentally, and I am taking it with me as a shorthand "handle" for this whole idea. I find it works well as a surface-level counter for the (alas, still inappropriately compelling) idea that a dumb algorithm can't get more accurate results than a smart observer.
2DSimon
Another possible metaphor is the pocket calculator. It can find a number for any expression you can put into it, and in most cases it can do it way faster and more accurately than a human could. However, that doesn't make it a replacement for a human. An intelligent agent like a human is still needed for the crucial part of figuring out what expression would be meaningful to put into it.
0handoflixue
That is a very helpful metaphor for wrapping my head around both the advantages and limitations of SPR, thank you! :)
[-]Dmytry-20

To think about it, the main critique i have for this article is:

  • Only lists cases where SPR 'outperformed' expertise. Of which in most we just loosely describe as 'experts' some people who had never did any proper training (with exercises and testing) to perform task in question.

  • Equates better correlation with "outperforms". Not the same thing. The maximum correlation happens when you classify into those with less than average risk of recidivism and those with larger than average risk. Parole board is not even supposed to work like this AFAIK.

... (read more)