I recently read Bryan Caplan's The Myth Of The Rational Voter. It's an excellent book in a lot of ways, and one of those ways is how it got me thinking about the issue of expert consensus. It's pushed me more towards thinking that hard data on what the experts in a given field believe about their area of expertise is incredibly useful. Specifically, based on examples from a variety of fields (listed below the fold), I'll conclude:

  • When the data show an overwhelming consensus in favor of one view (say, if the number of dissenters is less than the Lizardman's Constant), this almost always ought to swamp any other evidence a non-expert might think they have regarding the issue.
  • When a strong but not overwhelming majority of experts favor one view, non-experts should take this as strong evidence in favor of that view, but there's a greater chance that evidence could be overcome by other evidence (even from a non-expert's point of view). 
  • When there is only barely a majority view among experts, or no agreement at all, this is much less informative than the previous two conditions. It may indicate agnosticism is the appropriate attitude, but in many cases non-experts needn't hesitate before having their own opinion.
  • Expert opinion should be discounted when their opinions could be predicted solely from information not relevant to the truth of the claims. This may be the only reliable, easy heuristic a non-expert can use to figure out a particular group of experts should not be trusted.
Notable incidental conclusions relating to specific fields include:
  • Economics doesn't have the kind of overwhelming consensus you find on some issues in the natural sciences, but there still seem to be a lot of things most economists agree on.
  • Atheists shouldn't be timid about citing the majority opinion of philosophers as evidence for atheism.
  • Non-experts should default to thinking probably there was a historical Jesus.
  • You should really seriously accept the mainstream scientific consensus on global warming.

Evolution

The efforts of the anti-evolution movement have had the unintended consequence of making many people, especially in the atheist/rationalist/skeptic community, especially well aware of just how strong the evidence for evolution is. Unusually good explanations of the evidence for evolution is available in books and websites. And the hard data on support for evolution among scientists is pretty much what you'd expect. Wikipedia has a good summary of this data. 

Particularly noteworthy is a Pew poll that found that 97% of American scientists (as opposed to 61% of the general public) accept that humans and other living things have evolved over time. 87% of scientists (as opposed to a mere 32% of the general public) agree that evolution occurred due to natural processes, while only 8% of scientists claim evolution was guided by a supreme being.

It is a little hard to know what to make of this 8% number, especially given that a majority of scientists say they believe in God or a higher power. The 8% may include so-called "theistic evolutionists," who claim God worked through natural mechanisms of evolution to create life, but it may also include Michael Behe-style views that evolution could not have occurred through purely natural processes. The Pew poll doesn't tell us how many of each type of view is included in the 8%. However, other evidence suggests even Behe-style views are extremely rare among scientists, especially those with training relevant to the evolution controversy. Compare, for example, the Discovery Institute's "Dissent from Darwin" list to the National Center for Science Education's Project Steve.

In total, based both having spent a considerable amount of time following the creation-evolution controversy, and the overwhelming support that evolution enjoys among scientists, I think those who accept the scientific consensus on evolution are safe saying something like: "Given the overwhelming scientific consensus on evolution, it's extraordinarily unlikely that you know something all those scientists don't, or that there's a conspiracy to suppress the evidence for creationism. If you're not willing to just trust the scientists, here are some books and websites for you to read, but I'm not going to argue with you about it."

Economics

Expert opinion plays a central role in Caplan's Myth of the Rational Voter. Caplan argues that voters aren't just ill-informed about many topics, they suffer from biases that lead them to have views that systematically differ from those of the experts. And Caplan focuses on economics, both because it's his own area of expertise and because of it's obvious relevance for policy making.

I've heard The Myth of the Rational Voter described as having a "libertarian" perspective, but while Caplan is himself a libertarian, that didn't strike me as coming across particularly strongly in the book. I say this as someone who considers himself a fan of Paul Krugman, and in fact Caplan frequently cites Krugman in support of his points.

Furthermore, Caplan has hard data to back his claims up: one study found that, in 2000, 72.5% of economists mainly agreed with the claim that "tariffs and import quotas usually reduce the general welfare of society." A further 20.1% said they "agreed with provisos," while only 6% "generally disagreed." In another example Caplan cites, nearly three-quarters of economists generally disagreed with the statement "wage-price controls should be used to control inflation."

However, these numbers are not as overwhelming as the numbers on scientific support for evolution. And Caplan does not mind sometimes rejecting the majority view among his colleagues. He writes:

If my premise is that the economic consensus is reliable, how can I reach a conclusion that the economic consensus rejects?...

This complaint would be airtight if my premise were that the economic consensus is infallible. But my actual premise is merely that economists, like other experts, deserve the benefit of the doubt—and that the burden of proof rests on those who would question the expert consensus. Since the rational voter assumption is part of that consensus, my responsibility as a naysayer is to refute it—which is precisely why I needed to wrote this book.

I take it there's a connection between the fact that consensus in economics tends to be weaker, and Caplan's willingness to contradict the consensus on some issues. As a majority gets smaller, the chances that a scholar with the minority position might have good reasons to reject the minority view gets larger. Furthermore, when the majority view only has around 70%-75% of experts in its favor, it's also much more plausible that an informed layman could have good reasons to reject the majority view. Even though I'm not an economist, I don't hesitate to think Caplan is probably right to reject the rational voter assumption. Still, non-experts who have who know little about a debate should generally be willing to accept the conclusions of a 70+% majority.

Also relevant: Krugman himself has written about the issue of consensus in economics. His conclusion is that "most of what economists do is indeed fairly objective and non-ideological," and can produce considerable agreement among economists. However, there are some important issues in business-cycle macroeconomics where there are big, ideologically-driven disagreements. Even so, he notes that in one panel of 42 economists from top schools, 80% agreed with the statement that the 2009 American Reinvestment and Recovery Act "significantly boosted output and employment."

Something I almost forgot to mention, because it seems obvious to me, but probably doesn't seem obvious to other people: the views of economists probably can't be explained away as driven by political ideology. Anecdotally, people like Krugman are a problem for attempts to dismiss economists as libertarian ideologues (though I guess some people would dismiss Krugman as a neo-liberal sellout).

Furthermore, Caplan argues that data from the Survey of Americans and Economists on the Economy suggests the opinions of economists mostly cannot be explained as the result of ideology or socioeconomic class. He notes that, in spite of occasional accusations of "free-market fundamentalism" hurled at economists, the reality is that economists are acutely aware of the weaknesses of markets.

Philosophy

This is my own field, as much as someone who's left academia can claim a field as his own. And in philosophy, we have unusually good data about what professional philosophers believe about the major disputes in their field, thanks to a 2009 survey organized by philosophers David Bourget and David Chalmers through the website PhilPapers.org.

Robin Hanson commented when the survey data was released, and seemed happy to learn he agreed with the modal expert opinion on 25 out of the 30 questions surveyed. But this seemed to me, and still seems to me, the wrong reaction, given that on most questions there was no majority view. On the questions where there was a majority view, on about half of those there was still a large amount of disagreement, with less than 60% of philosophers accepting the majority view.

Under such circumstances, I'm inclined to think the opinion of the experts tells us very little about what the right view is. My reaction was partly colored by experience within philosophy, which has led me to think most philosophers don't have very good reasons for their philosophical opinions and agnosticism towards particular questions is more often the right view than most philosophers would admit.

It's interesting, though, to look at look at the three questions where there was most agreement. 81.6% of philosophers endorse non-skeptical realism about the external world, 75.1% endorse scientific realism, and 72.8% endorse atheism. Note that on all questions, there was a significant number of "other" answers, for example, on God, only 14.6% of philosophers endorsed theism, 5.5% were agnostic, while others endorsed various idiosyncratic views.

My initial reaction to these numbers were that they were the exceptions that proved the rule. "Non-skeptical realism about the external world," is basically just the claim that there's stuff (tables and chairs and trees and rocks and so on, or perhaps subatomic particles) that exists outside our minds and we can know about them. The fact that only about 80% of philosophers are able to agree on this seemingly commonsensical proposition just underlines how incapable of agreeing about anything philosophers are.

Scientific realism, similarly, is just the view that science describes the real world, and the less-than-total agreement of philosophers on this idea is similarly disappointing. The question of God's existence, meanwhile, strikes me as having more in common with the question of whether fairies exist than most other questions on the survey.

Yet as I've thought about the question more, particularly philosopher's opinions on God's existence, I've shifted towards thinking there are some questions where a strong majority of philosophers agreeing is significant. For one thing, it's striking how few theistic philosophers are interested in defending traditional arguments for the existence of God. With a few exceptions (most notably Richard Swinburne and William Lane Craig), they stick to arguing that belief in God is reasonable. That certainly seems worth mentioning if you're an atheist trying to persuade theists that there are no good arguments for the existence of God.

Reading The Myth of the Rational Voter caused my views to shift further, because it made me realize the level of agreement you'll find among philosophers on the external world, science, and God is about as high as you'll find among economists on major questions of economics. This makes me think that probably atheists should not be shy citing strong support for atheism among philosophers as a reason to be an atheist. I wouldn't claim it's conclusive all by itself, but it does create a presumption that atheism is the most rational view, which should place a strong burden of proof on the theist to overcome.

Arguably, there's also a lesson here for philosophy professors teaching undergrads (particularly in 101 classes). The standard approach to teaching philosophy is to make a show of being very even-handed in presenting any given debate, at most subtly prodding students towards the professor's preferred view. But it might be better for professors to be unapologetic about explaining to students that most philosophers are atheists and why.

The value of taking the same approach to knowledge of the external world and science may be less obvious, but I suspect it may be even more important. Too many undergraduates come out of their philosophy 101 classes thinking the lesson of philosophy is that we don't really know anything, or that science is a matter of faith too. Philosophy professors should consider trying to actively fight that tendency.

(What about the other issues that had relatively high levels agreement among philosophers? Professors might make a point of defending them too, though the next four most agreed-upon points from the PhilPapers survey aren't as exciting: the a priori, the analytic/synthetic distinction, the trolley problem, and cognitivism about moral judgement. At least, they're not as exciting until you connect them to other, more controversial, issues.)

The broader lesson I take away from this is that you don't need to worry about looking for the kind of symptoms that Luke has cited in diagnosing philosophy as a "diseased discipline." The example of philosophy suggests that when a group of experts is deeply confused about the subject-matter of their own discipline, they mostly fail to converge on any kind of strong majority agreement. That means all a non-expert needs to do is look at the data on expert opinion and if there's no strong majority agreement, they should feel pretty comfortable ignoring the experts when they feel it's necessary to do so.

And yes, though I'm inclined towards agnosticism on a lot of philosophical questions, that does mean it's often OK for non-philosophers to have strong opinions on philosophical questions that philosophers themselves can't agree on. For example, I think Eliezer should feel pretty comfortable with his advocacy of one-boxing on Newcomb's problem, even though a plurality of philosophers support two-boxing.

Philosophy vs. philosophy of religion

There's an important side-note to make here regarding the opinions of specialists in philosophy of religion. They, unlike professional philosophy as a whole, tend to be theists; 72.3% theists vs. 19.1% atheists. Some theistic philosophy-bloggers took this as vindication of theism, arguing philosophy of religion specialists know the most about the issues so they're who we should trust. On the other hand, it looks suspicious that they haven't managed to convince their colleagues in other specialties. What should we make of this?

The answer becomes obvious once you know a little more about the professional dynamics surrounding philosophy of religion. Philosophy of religion is not taken very seriously in mainstream philosophy. That is not a controversial point; philosophers of religion know it and complain about it. When I was at Notre Dame (the department rated number one for philosophy of religion in the world), one of the department's philosophers of religion specifically had the job of taking the religious grad students aside and telling them they had to specialize in something other than philosophy of religion or else they would not get a job.

This means atheist philosophers have basically no incentive to work in philosophy of religion. If you read the biographies of most philosophers of religion, overwhelmingly they were religious before they started studying philosophy and got into philosophy of religion because they really, really wanted to use philosophy to defend and/or elaborate on their religious beliefs. Even philosophers of religion are beginning to notice that philosophy of religion often resembles religious apologetics more than objective inquiry.

I'll save the technical account of why this matters for the section on Biblical scholarship, but here I'll note that it's hard to explain away mainstream support for atheism in a parallel manner. Academics do tend to be less religious than the general population, true, but philosophers are an outlier even among other academics. A 2009 study that looked at religious belief within the 20 largest academic disciplines found that only about 10 percent of academics are atheists, with psychologists being the most atheistic at 50 percent. 50 percent is extremely high compared to the general US population, but still not up to philosopher levels.

Biblical scholarship

I unfortunately don't have good data on the opinions of Biblical scholars, but I'm going to talk about it because it's an area I know a lot about (particularly historical Jesus research), and there's an important point to be made here about how non-experts can decide whether the opinions of experts are trustworthy.

The point is a rather obvious one: Christian apologists like William Lane Craig often cite the (alleged) consensus of Biblical scholarship in support of their arguments, but even if the basic claims were true, it wouldn't be to find that Biblical scholars tend to have views favorable to Christianity (and Judaism) because Biblical scholars are overwhelmingly Christians and Jews. Biblical scholars tend to get their degrees from seminaries rather than secular academic departments. Atheist Biblical scholar Jacques Berlinerblau once estimated that at a typical meeting of a thousand members of the Society for Biblical Literature, you'd find only a couple dozen atheists (I'm not sure if he meant to include people like Bart Ehrman, who identifies as an agnostic).

Non-believing Biblical scholars tend to be former believers who deconverted in part due to their studies; this is true of Bart Ehrman, Gerd Lüdemann, Michael Goulder, and Robert M. Price. Jacques Berlinerblau is an exception to the "former believers" rule. Hector Avalos is also a partial exception (his interest in the subject stems from his time a teen evangelist, but he deconverted before starting his graduate studies). I e-mailed Berlinerblau about this once, and he could think of one other scholar in the field who he didn't think had ever been a believer, but confirmed that such people are extraordinarily rare.

This doesn't mean that outside the few dozen atheists and agnostics, Biblical scholars are all going to agree with William Lane Craig, because there are also plenty of liberal Christians like John Dominic Crossan and Marcus Borg in Biblical scholarship. It does mean that if it did turn out that most Biblical scholars had views favorable to (traditional) Christianity, it wouldn't mean much because it would be no more surprising that finding out that Muslim scholars tend to have views favorable to Islam. It's the Crossans and the Borgs that are surprising (regardless of the exact liberal Christian / conservative Christian breakdown).

This common-sense argument in terms of what is and isn't surprising is reinforced by a Bayesian analysis: if the opinions of a group of experts can be predicted using information that isn't relevant to whether or not their opinions are true, knowing what their opinions are gives you no information on the claims in question. It's important to distinguish this heuristic from post hoc explaining away of expert opinions you don't like: conservative Christians often propose unflattering explanations for the opinions of the Crossans and the Ehrmans, but it's unlikely that they could have predicted their opinions using information not relevant to whether their opinions are right.

So far, I probably haven't said anything that would surprise the average member of LessWrong: of course Jesus didn't perform any miracles or rise from the dead. So let's tackle a slightly harder question: was there a historical Jesus at all? Or, to put it somewhat more precisely: can Christianity be traced back to the followers of a single Jewish preacher who was executed by the Roman authorities in Palestine in the first half of the first century A.D.?

That Christian scholars think Jesus existed isn't surprising. Even Crossan has his own version of the historical Jesus, as a wise teacher who's palatable to liberal churchgoers, that he wants to sell. Knowing the opinions of Crossan et al. may be slightly informative, since since many liberal Christian and Jewish scholars seem to have reconciled themselves to there being no historical Moses, so the fact that they haven't gone that route with Jesus may give us some information. But looking at the opinions of non-believing scholars specifically will be more informative.

Though we don't have survey data because non-believing Biblical scholars are so rare, and scholars who doubt Jesus' historicity even rarer, we can make an estimate. Richard Carrier (a historical Jesus skeptic with a PhD in history from Columbia University) recently listed Arthur Droge, Kurt Noll, and Thomas Thompson as people who "agree historicity agnosticism is warranted," in addition to listing Thomas Brodie, Robert M. Price, and himself as being "even more certain historicity is doubtful." Because historicity skeptics are so rare, and because Carrier knows the debate so well, this list is probably exhaustive at least as far as publicly expressed views are concerned.

There are a number of difficulties here. First, it's unclear whether Berlinerblau's "two dozen" estimate includes agnostics. Second, categorizing Carrier's list of skeptics gets tricky in a few cases. Robert M. Price is a non-believer who's officially agnostic on whether Jesus existed, but he's written a lot about the issue and is quite confident agnosticism is the right view, justifying his inclusion on the "more certain" list. Brodie has apparently tried to argue he can be a good Catholic while rejecting the idea of a historical Jesus (which, as I've already noted, is a position some people have already taken on Moses). Noll describes himself as "theistic off the job and professionally agnostic."

Finally, Brodie has apparently been convinced there was no historical Jesus since the 1970s, but until recently was keeping quiet about it (for fear of the professional repercussions?) That raises the question of whether there might be other skeptics out there still in the closet. Still, I'd venture that probably at least 75% (Carrier's 6 divided by Berlinerblau's 24) of non-religious scholars with relevant expertise are at least fairly confident Jesus existed. Much of the remainder would be agnostic rather than full-blown mythicists. That would be strong, but not overwhelming, support for historicity.

Having read both defenses of historicity by people like Ehrman, and critiques by Robert M. Price and Earl Doherty (who's an amateur, but has Carrier's endorsement), my impression is that even ignoring head counts the historicists have the better of the argument. But Carrier has said he doesn't expect most scholars to agree with him without having seen his research and arguments. He'll be presenting those in a book which is slated for release early next year. I think the book probably won't persuade many people, but I don't think Carrier's approach is necessarily foolish. It's possible Carrier has some decisive evidence that other people just don't have access to, yet.

Climate science

Reference to global warming on LessWrong sometimes elicit negative reactions (often with references to a misinterpreted version of Politics is the Mind-Killer), yet on the merits global warming seems to be in the same situation as evolution. Wikipedia, again, has a good summary of the data on expert opinion, even better than the one for evolution. Highlights include:

  • The 2007 IPCC report concluded that, "Most of the observed increase in global average temperatures since the mid-20th century is very likely due to the observed increase in anthropogenic GHG concentrations," with "very likely" defined as >90% certainty.
  • A survey of members of the American Meteorological Society and American Geophysical Union found that 97% agreed that global temperatures had increased during the past 100 years and 84% agreed that human-caused warming was occurring.
  • Other studies suggest that, among the climatologists who are most active in publishing on the issue, support for the mainstream consensus on the causes of global warming is even higher: 97-98%.
I haven't spent as much time studying the global warming debate as I have studying the creation-evolution debate, but to the extent I have studied it, the evidence seems uniformly supportive of the view that human activity has caused significant warming. Reconstructions of past temperatures seem to show that current temperatures are the warmest we've had in 2000 years and possibly much longer. Importantly, while this may or may not be the first time global temperatures have been this high, the rate of warming since the mid-19th century seems to be truly unprecedented.

Michael Mann et al's so-called "hockey stick" graph has come under a lot of fire from skeptics, but (a) many other reconstructions have reached the same conclusion and (b) a panel formed by the National Research Council concluded that, while there were some problems with Mann et al's statistical analysis, these problems did not affect the conclusion. Furthermore, even if we didn't have the pre-1800 reconstructions, I understand that given what we know about CO2's heat-trapping properties, and given the increase in atmospheric CO2 levels due to burning fossil fuels, it would be surprising if humans hadn't caused significant warming.

Sometimes I regret not knowing the climate controversy as well as I know the evolution controversy, but what I've seen so far makes me think it's extremely likely that if I did study it in greater depth, doing so would just confirm the evolution-climate change parallel. Given that, it's probably not worth my time. So lately, when people have tried to argue with me about climate change, I've refused to argue with them just as I'd refuse to argue with a creationist. While I don't know of anything that's quite the equivalent of TalkOrigins for climate change, Wikipedia has an entire set of excellent (even by Wikipedia standards) articles on climate change and I'd recommend people who want to know more start there.

This is a good place to note how my analysis here differs from that in Vladimir_M's post "Some Heuristics for Evaluating the Soundness of the Academic Mainstream in Unfamiliar Fields." Vladmir suggests "ideological interest" as one of two signs that a discipline may be in bad shape, and suggests climate science as an example of this. Vladmir may for all I know be right about there being a fair amount of bad research out there on the likely effects of climate change, but in general I think merely noticing the potential for ideological bias in field shouldn't greatly weaken your confidence in the opinion of a strong majority of experts.

As discussed in the section on Biblical scholarship, the test you should be applying is whether you could predict the expert opinions on the basis of ideology, without needing to know anything about the relevant evidence. Dismissing a field merely based on the potential for ideological bias is an invitation to ignore any conclusion you don't like. After all, creationists have no trouble coming up with ways to explain away the scientific consensus about evolution in terms of ideology.

Other examples?

The above examples largely exhaust the cases I know about where a strong majority of experts agree on an issue, yet the issue is controversial among people outside the field. The age of the earth, the age of the universe, and the Big Bang are also technically examples because young earth creationism, but you already knew that.

However, I can think of some minor examples that seem to support the principle that when there's little to no agreement among the experts, non-experts should focus on other evidence if they're going to have an opinion. For example, there's currently no majority view among physicists on how to interpret quantum mechanics, and nothing strikes me as inherently foolish about Eliezer's advocacy of many-worlds. Similarly, though I don't have data my impression is that evolutionary biologists and psychologists are divided on evolutionary psychology, but I feel no hesitation in thinking that the basic tenets of evolutionary psychology are correct.

Can we find counter-examples to the heuristics suggested above? A case where, for non-obvious reasons, a strong majority of the experts in some field have converged on a crazy conclusion? The more heavily postmodern corners of academia might be a good place to look for that. In "The Myth of the Postmodern University," Brian Leiter argues that the influence of postmodernism on academia has been greatly exaggerated, but it has had significant impact on English, literature, and history. Leiter also quotes a reader e-mail suggesting that communication, media studies, cultural studies, and journalism may also belong on the of fields heavily influenced by postmodernism. So it may be worth looking at those.

But my guess is that there may be less there than meets the eye. I don't doubt you can find many people with crazy pomo ideas in those fields, but I suspect you'd also find lots of people in those same fields who generally reject the crazy pomo ideas. At worst, I'd expect to find 50-odd percent support for the crazy view with a significant number of objectors. But I may be wrong about this, and it would be helpful to find good data.

Another issue: it may seem surprising that I haven't been able to uncover clear evidence of a field corrupted by political ideology, the way philosophy of religion and Biblical scholarship are significantly corrupted by religious agendas. This may be because religions like Christianity have a fairly definite body of doctrine (left-wing theology aside), making bias easy to detect. Political categories like "liberal" or "conservative," on the other hand, are squishier, which plausibly makes bias harder to detect.

Indeed, though the effects may be less obvious, there does seem to be evidence for a general self-selection effect: liberal college students are more likely to pursue careers in academia. That certainly suggests you shouldn't vote for Democrats just because most college professors do, but it's unclear how it affects specific academic debates. The fact that even liberal economists tend to have many views that don't fit the liberal stereotype suggests these effects tend to get swamped by the effects of having relevant expertise, when someone's dealing with their own field. But perhaps there are other, less encouraging examples out there that I'm unaware of.

Finally, left-right political bias may be much less important than nationalistic bias. I once heard it said (by Orwell? Russell? Google isn't helping me find the quote) that if you're from a small country that hasn't played an important role in world affairs, you'll likely be able to find an objective history of your country written by a foreign historian, but otherwise you're probably out of luck for an objective history of your country. Among US historians, there's an obvious counter-point that people like Howard Zinn and James W. Loewen don't seem at all unusual. Which is not to say they're necessary very objective, just that the biases among US historians may run in enough different directions to prevent the entire history profession from converging on nonsense.

On the other hand, even among left-wing historians in the US, how many would go as far as gwern does and say the American Revolution was a mistake? Yet gwern seems to to have a strong case: it's definitely a bad thing when a war kills tens of thousands of people, and the US and Canada didn't turn out all that different. So, contrary to what many would expect, it may be that even left-wing US historians are too positive about America. This suggests that, on issues where nationalistic bias could be a problem, you should be cautious about accepting the majority opinion of historians unless you have international data.

Postcript

For some extra context for this post, see my discussion post on academic cliques.

New Comment
81 comments, sorted by Click to highlight new comments since:
Some comments are truncated due to high volume. (⌘F to expand all)Change truncation settings

I haven't spent as much time studying the global warming debate as I have studying the creation-evolution debate, but to the extent I have studied it, the evidence seems uniformly supportive of the view that human activity has caused significant warming.

I'll note that most of the resistance to global warming that I've seen on LW is not on these points. (Bias note: I think my position is roughly central of global warming resistance I've seen on LW, but if I err in describing opinion on LW it will be by pushing the opinion too far towards myself.) The evidence seems very solid that human activity has altered the atmospheric concentrations of CO2, and that this results in higher temperatures.

The primary issues are:

  • Predictive climate models are in a class of computational problems known to computational modeling experts to be extremely vulnerable to fudging. That is to say, by judicious choice of parameters, you can get the models to say basically whatever you'd like them to say, and the models make several assumptions which are obviously wrong which could totally nullify their predictive ability.
  • Climate science has incentives that seem unusually pointed away from truth-discovery
... (read more)

The question of which temperature / global climate is optimal is rarely discussed, suggesting that the current climate is unlikely to be optimal.

Agree that this topic is not widely discussed in mainstream climate science as such, but not sure your conclusion follows.

The chances of the current global climate being optimal would be pretty remote, except for the facts that one very powerful (but slow) optimisation process has been busy adapting the existing biota (including humans) to the climate, followed by an even more powerful and much more rapid optimisation process adapting human capital and expertise to the existing climate.

It's not that we can't adapt to another set of climate and weather patterns, it's that it'll have a cost. There certainly is a reasonable amount of discussion in the mainstream climate literature about the likely costs of adaptation. Which, of course, one needs to weigh against the likely benefits.

Predicting the local weather impact of global climate change is fearsomely difficult and uncertain (far more so than global temperature), which makes adding up the cost/benefit analysis extremely difficult. (And makes planning long-term capital investments difficult.)

It seems to me pretty likely that the current global climate is at least a local optimum for humans.

2Desrtopa
I think this depends on what you mean by "for humans." We're an equatorial species, and most of our global population is living in colder climates than most of our evolutionary adaptation was geared towards. However, humans are highly robust within a wide range of temperatures; many of the species we depend upon, less so.
0Vaniver
The first seems insignificant (given the second and the changing climate) and the second seems self-defeating (if we invented air conditioning to deal with the outside not being the correct temperature, it's not at all obvious that local air-conditioning is the best way to manage the climate, especially given the known issues with using local heat dumps in, say, cities). This is the point that I think is actually contentious in the wider world, but should not be.
0Lumifer
That seems unlikely. First, which one is optimal -- the one right now when we already warmed up a bit, or, say, the climate of mid-XIX century? And second, the already posted link shows that within a particular range of temperature and CO2 concentration increasing them increased the world's GDP. We are not at the end of that range so increasing the temperature and the CO2 further would get us closer to optimality -- meaning we're not there yet.
3satt
It takes some time for added CO₂ to exert its full effect on temperature. Because of that lag, I'd expect CO₂ levels to hit their optimum before temperature does, so it's worth considering them separately. The results at that link and in its underlying source suggest we're at (and maybe beyond) the optimum CO₂ level already. According to that paper, the temperature won't reach the calculated optimum of 1.2°C to 1.3°C until 2025. But the CO₂ level is already high enough that we're likely to overshoot that temperature unless we cut emissions aggressively.

Climate science has incentives that seem unusually pointed away from truth-discovery compared to other fields, and there seems to be evidence of climate scientists (rationally!) responding to those incentives.

Really? What kind of incentives?

This isn't an issue I care much about, so I hope you won't mind a quick treatment. The 5-second version is that more is on the line for the researchers personally with climate change research than other sorts of science, that scientific reports have consequences for politics which forces the scientists to be more involved in politics than other sorts of scientists, and that this corroding influence of politics adds friction to the processes that pump errors out of science. Here's an incomplete list with more details:

The most visible one is media pressure, which rewards more shocking possibilities. (Did you ever hear about clathrate gun hypothesis? Did you hear that further research didn't pan out?) In most other fields, the media rarely if ever comes calling, and so more of the incentives come from other researchers. (I remember a historian, who was called up because Sarah Palin had made a correct but non-obvious comment about Paul Revere, who pointed out that he had never been interviewed until Palin had mentioned Revere.)

Relatedly, the funding and visibility of climatology depends in large part on how much people care about climatology. This is true for many fields- NASA seems t... (read more)

1Lumifer
I am not sure I agree with that. I think I would phrase my position as "There is social benefit in providing data to absolutely everyone without any prequalifications". For example the Freedom of Information Act says government must provide certain kinds of information on request. It doesn't get to peek into the requester's mind and decide whether there was "bad faith" or "good faith". I think it's a very good thing that it doesn't. Similarly, I think science should provide supporting data to everyone who asks (subject to reasonable limits tied to the costs of providing data). In particular, scientists should stand ready to provide data to their worst critics regardless of what they think of their theories, competency, or fashion sense. And yes, Climategate brought into the open a rather large fail in that respect on the part of pro-warming crowd (among other things).
0Vaniver
Agreed that this is the most truth-seeking policy. I specified "social benefit" because I don't think the two line up.
-8Eugine_Nier
0[anonymous]
I hope nobody just starts listing incentives here, but also explains what's unusual about them.
0[anonymous]
Yeah, that "compared to other fields" part confuses me too.
3ChrisHallquist
Upvoted. This is much better than other reactions I've seen to discussion of global warming on LW, which often amount to knee-jerk downvoting paired with comments that amount to "global warming is politics and politics is the mindkiller!" That said, regarding what climate is optimal, that's not something that can be answered in isolation. Existing people and ecosystems are adapted to current conditions, so it isn't surprising that rapid change away from those conditions would cause problems, at least on net (and note that the IPCC doesn't claim effects of global warming will be universally negative, just negative on net). It's like how a flood is a bigger problem than water that's always been there. Same thing with sea levels rising - it means people need to move or build dikes or something, which is costly.

Hat tip to Robin Hanson:

Climate change / global warming is real and man-made. It will come as a big surprise that climate change from 1900 to 2025 has mostly been a net benefit, rising to increase welfare about 1.5% of GDP per year. Why? Because global warming has mixed effects and for moderate warming, the benefits prevail. The increased level of CO₂ has boosted agriculture because it works as a fertilizer and makes up the biggest positive impact at 0.8% of GDP. Likewise, moderate warming avoids more cold deaths than it incurs extra heat deaths. It also reduces the demand for heating more than increases the costs of cooling, totaling about 0.4%. On the other hand, warming increases water stress at about 0.2% and negatively impact ecosystems like wetlands at about 0.1%. Storm impacts are very small, as the total storm damages (including naturally caused storms) are about 0.2%.

As temperatures rise, the costs will rise and the benefits decline, leading to a dramatic reduction in net benefits. After year 2070, global warming will become a net cost to the world, justifying cost-effective climate action.

1ChrisHallquist
Sounds plausible.
0roystgnr
The best reaction I've seen to discussion of global warming anywhere was on LW. Your post here is much better about specifically defining what the "expert consensus" says, but note that it's a bar so low that all the well-informed "skeptics"/"deniers" I've read would agree with the majority of AGW experts on the second bullet point.
7ChrisHallquist
I saw that thread too, and was horrified - horrified that people were downvoting Stuart. And actually, on reflection, that that comment was upvoted is pretty horrifying too. The comment claims ambiguity in Stuart's post when there is none: it brings up value judgments and policy and so on when Stuart was very specific that he was talking about denial of the very existence of AGW, rather than about disagreements on appropriate policy responses. That tells me the commenter - and everyone who voted it up - was emotionally uncomfortable with the idea that AGW delialists were just completely wrong, so they read ambiguity into Stuart's statement that wasn't there.
[-]Jiro100

The problem with saying "I'm only talking about X, I'm not talking about Y" when Y is related to X but less extreme, is that in politics people who are Y are often caricatured as being X. It's pretty hard to tell the difference between someone who really means to attack X and only X, and someone who is attacking Y by implicitly accusing them of being X and then attacking X.

It's the same reason as to why Jews might feel themselves to be a target when someone argues how bad it is to kill Christian babies to use their blood to bake matzohs, even if they have not personally killed any babies. Certainly if anyone posted such an argument I'd mod them down, even if I agreed that it's bad to eat babies and that they have correctly stated why.

4JoshuaZ
This is a really bad example in this context. It would only be similar if there were some people who were actually using blood to bake their matzohs. When X and Y both actually exist, the situation is different.
2Jiro
If that's how you feel, replace it with "greedy Jewish bankers". Real ones exist, but it's unlikely that someone complaining about them is limiting his complaints to the ones that exist--he's probably saying it because he thinks there are more greedy Jewish bankers than there really are. The point is that it may make sense to object to an otherwise legitimate attack on a group that doesn't include you if the attacker thinks that the group includes you.
4JoshuaZ
I'm not sure that's a good comparison either, although it is slightly better. In that context, there'd be a legitimate complaint possibly of "greedy bankers" but it is doubtful that "greedy bankers" is a subset of Jewish bankers. Not the case for the example in question.
6Vaniver
Strong disagreement. Stuart_Armstrong uses interchangeably the phrases "global warming denial," "someone who denies the existence of anthropogenic global warming (AGW)," and "global warming skeptic." There is significant ambiguity there- many people identify as "global warming skeptics" in that they are skeptical of the moral and political claims of the global warming movement, not that they deny the existence of AGW. Similarly, many people identify as "global warming deniers" because they deny the moral, predictive, or prescriptive claims put forward by the global warming movement. (Note that Thomas, who did express doubt in AGW, got downvoted to -3.) I didn't see any effort on Stuart_Armstrong's part to disambiguate those or notice that he needed to. For example, in your post, it looked like you carefully limited the consensus to the actual scientific consensus on historical anthropogenic climate change, and if Stuart_Armstrong had mentioned that he was just talking about the historical record, there wouldn't have been a need for steven0461's comment. Note this subthread in particular.
5buybuydandavis
I'm not skeptical of CO2 as a greenhouse gas, or of the increase of atmospheric CO2, or that increasing CO2 levels will generally lead to higher temperatures, or that we have had higher temperatures in the last few decades. But I am skeptical of the model projections into the future, and even more skeptical of the claims that the accuracy of those models have been established when they've proven inaccurate for the last decade. When you make predictions that fail, you should be decreasing your certainty in the model that gave those predictions.
0Vaniver
I put "predictive or prescriptive claims" into my second bit, but I probably should have included it there as well.
2ChrisHallquist
That demands seems a little strange. Should he have disclaimed any claim about future warming? But given past warming caused by human CO2 (and other) emissions, we should expect more warming if we continue that activity (actually, the IPCC thinks warming would continue even if CO2 were kept at current levels). On the other hand, I'm not seeing any way to read Stuart's statement as anything like, "if your estimate of future warming is only 50% of the estimate I prefer you're irrational."

Another issue: it may seem surprising that I haven't been able to uncover clear evidence of a field corrupted by political ideology, the way philosophy of religion and Biblical scholarship are significantly corrupted by religious agendas.

"Women's studies"? (I'm sure they're pretty much spot-on about many things, but it's also seems like the kind of environment where people can go off the deep end.)

In my personal contact with this crowd (women's studies, not sociology, to be clear), I've often been quite frustrated. When approached in a reasonable manner, at least those I've encountered have been reasonable in return, willing to seriously discuss problems and alternative theories. But in their public statements and publications they go to great lengths to avoid expressing any doubt or disagreement with one another or with the orthodoxy in the field. I suppose they feel solidarity is necessary in the face of outside threats, and I'm not unaware that they do in fact face outside threats, but this still seems to me like a problem.

2TheAncientGeek
Sociology?

I think there's a wrench in the historical Jesus example. While a majority of Biblical scholars agree that he existed, there's almost no consensus about who he was, which seems to be the driving force behind those who are agnostic or skeptical about Jesus' existence. In other words, there's a consensus about Jesus' historicity but there's no consensus about why he was actually important to early Christians. Which is strange.

As a matter of fact, there's a huge halo effect bias among Biblical scholars when describing Jesus in a supposed secular academic con... (read more)

4ChrisHallquist
As I discuss here, the Bart Ehrman claims that the "apocalyptic Jesus" (which gives you a very flawed Jesus, what with him wrongly predicting the end of the world) was "probably by the majority of scholars over the course of the century, at least in German and America." However, there's some dispute over what the current distribution of opinion is, so I left the issue out of my post. The range of opinion on who Jesus was is still not entirely encouraging - but you still have a large number of scholars (whether a majority currently or just a large minority) supporting a view that I find independently plausible, which makes me feel pretty good about thinking that view is probably right.

I think your point on the lack of consensus in philosophy is somewhat unfair. A lot of questions in the survey were chosen because they were hard or unsolved problems. A similar survey of unsolved hard questions in physics would also produce split answers. (for example ask if there actually an island of stability at higher atomic numbers).

On the easy questions, consensus seemed to be 95%+ once you threw out the 14% of theists (assume them to choose the answer logically required by theism) and people choosing "other".

2ChrisHallquist
These are good thoughts, but my experience in philosophy doesn't bear them out. You do find people in philosophy claiming "ah, we don't agree on the big questions, but on these smaller questions there's a consensus." In my experience, though, these claims never stand up to close scrutiny. On your specific suggestion, while theism is certainly correlated with certain positions (like libertarian free will and dualism), the correlation is not as strong as you might think. For example, I think Michael Rae, who was my metaphysics professor at Notre Dame, was a theist and sympathetic to compatibilist views about free will. Peter van Inwagen, a leading metaphysician and philosopher of religion, is a theist but takes a materialist view of the human mind, and sees the afterlife as being purely a matter of God resurrecting people's physical bodies. The philpapers survey data bears this out: if you look at the population of philosophers of religion, there are more theists than libertarians or people with non-physicalist views of the mind. And I'm pretty sure that's in spite of the fact that some of the atheists and agnostics who specialize in philosophy of religion are dualists and/or libertarians: for example, Paul Draper is an agnostic and a libertarian. Even ignoring that, not quite sure how you got the "95%+ if you ignore theists" conclusion. On free will, ignore the libertarians if you like but the compatibilists outnumber the no-free-will folks 5:1, not 20:1. Or in philosophy of mind, you could subtract 14% from the "non-phsycalism" number and only get about a 4:1 ratio of physicalists:non-physicalists.
-2William_Quixote
Based on your claim that many theists don’t hold the views that seem to obviously pair with theism, my whole approach may be off, but for the sake of transparency the questions I looked at for my (admittedly loosely calculated) claim of “95% on easy questions excluding theists and other” were as follows: All results sorted by course rather than fine I kicked out other and assumed strong overlap with theists and opposing scientific realism I kicked out other and assumed strong overlap with theists and non physicalism. This is slightly below average for the level of consensus among things I was thinking about I kicked out other and theists and shockingly got near 100% agreement afterwards. I kicked out other and assumed strong overlap with theists and libertarianism. I further grouped no free will and compatibilists since compatibilists basically believe “no free will” if you interpret the phrase as having its common language meaning. Compatibleism claims the common langue concept is somewhat incoherent and offers a different but related concept that gets the same name but doesn’t mean the same thing. If you reduce the question to a binary, compatbislm is on the other side from libertarianism. Kick out other
5ChrisHallquist
So I hadn't checked this, but it turns out the survey did report correlation data. Link to correlation data for belief in God. Some highlights: * ~22% of theists are physicalists. The ratio of physicalists:non-physicalists among atheists is about 3:1. * Only 50% of theists accept the libertarian view of free will, but hardly any (<8% of) atheists do. * Theism is slightly correlated with scientific anti-realism, but only slightly. 70% of theists are scientific realists and and >10% of atheists are scientific anti-realists. * Shockingly, to me, ~17.7% of theists are moral anti-realists. Unlike the free will and philosophy of mind cases, I have no idea who these people are or what they're thinking. Also, you're making some questionable assumptions about compatibilism. Many compatibilists would claim their definition of free will does match the common language understanding, and there's some x-phi work that backs this up (done by Eddy Nahmias).
7Nornagest
"There's no objective morality, but God has the biggest stick"? That's my best guess, anyway.
0TheAncientGeek
If a physicalist can think ethical subjectivism can work, why not a thesis?
0William_Quixote
Wow! Those correlations are very surprising to me. I didn't bother checking because it had seemed obvious to me that a theist must believe in a non physical enduring self or moral realism. I'm glad you asked me for more detail because my initial assumptions were way off.
-2hairyfigment
Not sure what you think this means, aside from the fact that philosophers use a lot of confused terminology. The point about physicalism seems more disturbing. By the way, I was also unpleasantly surprised to look at this recommended article from Nous - the supposedly high-quality philosophy periodical - and see no mention of Judea Pearl, nor any obvious discussion of the fact that people may have different goals or interests. The author doesn't give me the impression she's trying to solve the (alleged) problem of Sobel counterfactuals.

"That means all a non-expert needs to do is look at the data on expert opinion and if there's no strong majority agreement, they should feel pretty comfortable ignoring the experts when they feel it's necessary to do so."

If experts are divided on a yes-no question, you may have a sizable chance of being right if you go with the minority view. But that does not mean that the strategy of going with your personal judgment will outperform the strategy of going with modal or plurality expert opinion (or systematically transformed opinion).

0ChrisHallquist
It's simplistic to divide possible strategies into "go with your personal judgment" and "go with modal / plurality expert opinion." You can, for example, mostly do the latter except on issues you've studied carefully and seem to have strong reasons for embracing the minority view on. There's also different degrees of certainty you can have. Often, I think the right think to do is to weakly incline towards the modal / plurality view.
1Thrasymachus
I'd be even less inclined to go with personal judgment than you stake out here. Even if I study something carefully and evenhandedly and am generally smart, you shouldn't take my view on subject X to be on epistemic par with the central-measure expert on subject X (who is also generally smart but will have studied a subject a lot more than me). If there was a weak plurarity of experts on one view, but I was dissenting, you would still think the best bet would be to go with the plurality of experts, despite my carefully studied dissent. So what changes, taking the outside view, if the well-studied amateur dissent happens to be your own?
0Lumifer
That sounds suspiciously like "So who are you going to believe, me or your own lying eyes?"

Howard Zinn

I don't think using Zinn as an example of objective work is going to work well. Many historians have criticized Zinn. One of the more disturbing criticisms is a complete failure to update known issues when going to later editions of his book. Loewen seems like a substantially better example in this context.

2ChrisHallquist
Sorry if I wasn't clear enough about that. I didn't mean to cite Zinn as objective. I meant to cite him as a counter-example to the suggestion that US historians might be dominated by one particular set of biases. I tried to indicate this by saying, "it does suggest the biases will run in enough different directions to prevent the entire history profession from converging on nonsense." (EDIT: tried to tweak the wording to make this clearer.)
[-]satt30

A little editorial nitpick.

Among US historians, there's an obvious counter-point that people like Howard Zinn and James W. Loewen don't at all unusual.

Is there a verb like "seem" missing between "don't" & "at"?

2ChrisHallquist
D'oh. Thanks, fixed.
[-][anonymous]20

Bit of an aside, but have you read Reza Aslan's Zealot, and if so what are your thoughts? Reza Aslan is another interesting point here as he doubted his faith during his studies, although instead of becoming agnostic he reverted back to Islam.

However I brought up the book more because it provides a middle way out. Aslan's historical Jesus is someone very different from the Christ figure, whose existence seems more plausible than fabrication given the scale involved. There was, after all, an active cult of his followers in Jerusalem for decades after his de... (read more)

2hairyfigment
Have you seen Carrier's description of the sub-lunar Jesus theory? This says that the first Christians thought Jesus lived in some heavenly realm, a belief which apparently had precedent in the Roman world. (Carrier doesn't mention the idea that Paul thought "Jesus" lived on Earth, but much earlier than the standard date derived from the Gospels. The self-appointed or vision-appointed disciple could have changed the way people thought about some alleged Teacher from long ago.) In any case, Paul would supposedly have learned a rhetorical style that had people shorten a long phrase like "brothers of the Lord" most of the time, only occasionally using the full phrase for emphasis. And he certainly calls Christians "brothers" many times. The fact that he only seems to use the long phrase in connection with one name is Bayesian evidence against this theory. I don't know if that matters or not. My opinion on this subject is generally wishy-washy. But for completeness, I should say that I think Paul refers to exactly two events in the life of Jesus - the Crucifixion and the Last Supper - and Mark's earliest account has some pretty explicitly allegorical parts. (Compare the first link to verses 28-29 in the second.)

N00b question here. Are mainstream academic philosopher's interested in consensus?

1ChrisHallquist
Not officially, I guess, but many will try to dismiss objections to their views by saying "oh, I've got a consensus on my side" (when they don't). See here. Edit: added a link to the same post as a postscript.
0Laoch
Is this an example of a diseased discipline? Philosophers explore conceptual space. Mathematicians explore number space I guess? Yet the latter seems less fractured as discipline at least by my understanding which is probably pitiful.
2Shmi
As discussed recently, there are plenty of cliques in math, physics and other communities, as well. Scientists are fallible.
0Laoch
No doubt, but in science there is an expectation of consensus for the science to be useful.
1Lumifer
For science to be useful it has to adequately reflect reality. Consensus is entirely irrelevant.
0TheAncientGeek
How is reflection of reality verified?
0Lumifer
Empirically.
0TheAncientGeek
And when you have N empircally adequate theories..?
0Lumifer
Then you are indifferent between them and can choose on e.g. aesthetic criteria.
2TheAncientGeek
Consensus sounds better.
0Lumifer
It also means something different.
2TheAncientGeek
Yes. The thing it means, which is not the the thing "aesthetics" means, is better.
0Lumifer
Ah. Well then.

There's a problem if two groups of experts claim responsibility for the same question and answer it differently. The example I have in mind is doctors vs. psychotherapists on ADHD, but I'm sure there are many others.

It's easy, but not helpful, to use "postmodern" as a shorthand for "bad ideas" of some kind. Something like Sturgeon's law ("90% of everything is crap") applies to postmodernism as to everything else, and I'd even agree that it's a kind of thinking that is more likely than average to come unmoored from reality, but that doesn't mean that it's barren of all insight. Especially today, at least 20 years after its heydey, and considering that even in its heyday it was a very rare academic department indeed where drinking the kool-... (read more)

my impression is that even ignoring head counts the historicists have the better of the argument.

Why? I haven't looked into it much, but it looks to me like they've ignored alternative hypotheses (and that they met with mythicism first in the form of crack-pottery). Can you point me to about 2 decibels of evidence you don't think I've seen?

Also, this looks like a mistake:

possible Carrier has some decisive decisive evidence

4ChrisHallquist
If you look closely at the gospels, it sure looks like Jesus was a failed apocalyptic preacher, who wrongly predicted the ends of the world within his lifetime / lifetime of his contemporaries. If so, he wouldn't have been the only one in the area at the time, and there is precedent for apocalyptic movements surviving and mutating after their original predictions failed. (See Millerites --> Seventh Day Adventists.) Also, hypothesis that Jesus was originally a divine being is at odds with indications that the divinity of Jesus wasn't originally part of Christian thought, but something that developed in stages. Thanks, fixed.
0hairyfigment
I've seen these assertions before, of course, and the object-level parts may well be correct. But when I "look closely" at this, it "sure looks like" a metaphor for the destruction of the Temple. To the point where it seems natural to doubt that Mark intended anyone to read any of his original work literally. And the oldest ending in our possession likewise "looks like" a metaphor for the same events. Orson Scott Card put a lot of his religion in the first four Ender books, but I doubt you could ever converge on his actual beliefs if you only had the text to go on.
0JQuinton
The genre of Mark seems to be what most scholars rely on to arrive at the failed apocalyptic prophet conclusion, reading Mark as a Greco-Roman biography (Ehrman's position). But that looks to be seriously unfounded and, as you point out, it seems as though Mark is more like an allegorical Jewish novel. The verses you linked to about the unripe fig tree? The area that Jesus is close to is called Bethphage... which means "house of unripe figs".
[-]Shmi-20

This seems like a Procrustean-bed attempt at forcing disparate areas of human endeavor into a single reference class of "fields of expertise" in order to use an outside view to evaluate the correlation between expert consensus and trustworthiness. It is understandably tempting, since, if successful, it would give an outsider a tool to evaluate the reliability of the experts' statements. Unfortunately, these "fields of expertise" are vastly different. Some use the scientific method, like biology and environmental sciences, and maybe econ... (read more)

2ChrisHallquist
My impression is that bias sometimes produces majority opinions, sometimes even fairly large majorities in the 70-80% range, but rarely produces anything like >95% majorities, and when it does the causes are going to be obvious like religion and nationalism. Do you have a counter-example?
5Shmi
I don't have the stats to make one, sorry. The idea of continental drift was shunned by the experts for a long time. It took decades for astronomers to start taking black holes seriously. The germ theory of disease was not an instant hit, either. The heliocentric view. Troy being a real place. I am not sure about percentages in any of these cases.
5ChrisHallquist
Was the reluctance of scientists to accept these ideas the result of bias? Do you think non-experts of the time could have figured out these ideas were correct?
8Protagoras
In the case of the heliocentric view, it would have been hard for anybody to find evidence for the correct view prior to the observations of Tycho Brahe. The earlier observations were too imprecise and error-filled to be much help in distinguishing between the leading hypotheses; Copernicus wasn't notably better or worse at explaining the older data than Ptolemy. But Brahe's far superior data showed that they both had to be wrong, and Kepler's heliocentric view was the only theory that managed to fit Brahe's much more precise observations (and Copernicus got perhaps undeserved retroactive credit for also being heliocentric, even though he got the details quite wrong). I'm not as familiar with the others, but at least in the case of Troy and black holes I can see plenty of legitimate justification for the experts being skeptical before really strong new evidence emerged.
2EHeller
I'd go farther and note that Kepler was the real iconoclast, in that he didn't simply throw more epicycles into either the Copernican or the Ptolemaic model.
0Douglas_Knight
Do you have a quantitative statement of the error bars on normal (ie, not Brahe) astronomical data? I have heard it claimed that Ptolemy's data is systematically biased in favor of his model, which is only meaningful if the error bars are small enough that such data could distinguish models. (though there's also the issue of whether anyone understood error bars)
0hairyfigment
IAWYC, but note that Copernicus pointed out a real problem with the existing Aristotelian theory. The physics (or natural philosophy) underlying Ptolemy said that the minds associated with the heavens, by contemplating perfect activity, moved in regular circles. If you try to take these motions literally, it doesn't work - you need a non-circular motion to turn the "equant" into a mechanical explanation. While we could easily hand-wave this, it still made sense to look for other explanations. So Copernicus had something besides pure luck going for him.
1Protagoras
But Copernicus also tried to make the heavenly bodies move in circles. Kepler was the one who finally threw that mistake out.