It seems obvious that people are using "universally compelling arguments" in two different senses.
In the first sense, a universally compelling argument is one that could convince even a rock, or a mind that doesn't implement modus ponens, or a mind with anti-inductive priors. In this sense, the lack of universally compelling arguments for any domain (math/physics/morality) seems sufficiently well established.
In another sense, a universally compelling argument is one that could persuade any sufficiently sane/intelligent mind. I think we can agree that all such minds will eventually conclude that relativity and quantum mechanics are correct (or at least a rough approximation to whatever the true laws of physics end up being), so in this sense we can call the arguments that lead to them universally compelling. Likewise, in this sense, we can note as interesting the non-existence of universally compelling arguments which could compel a sufficiently sane/intelligent paperclipper to value life, beauty, justice, and the American way. It becomes more interesting if we also consider the case of babyeaters, pebblesorters, or humans with values sufficiently different to our own.
You are using the term in the first sense, but the people who are bothered by it are using it in the second sense.
Except that "sufficiently sane/intelligent" here just means, it seems, "implements modus ponens, has inductive priors, etc." We can, like Nick Tarleton, simply define as "not a mind" any entity or process that doesn't implement these criteria for sufficient sanity/intelligence...
... but then we are basically saying: any mind that is not convinced by what we think should be universally compelling arguments, is not a mind.
That seems like a dodge, at best.
Are there different criteria for sufficient sanity and intelligence, ones not motivated by the matter of (allegedly) universally compelling arguments?
Even a token effort to steelman the "universally" in "universally compelling arguments" yields interesting results.
Consider a mind that thinks the following:
But don't consider it very long, because it drank the poison and now it's dead and not a mind anymore.
If we restrict our observations to minds that are capable of functioning in a moderately complex environment, UCAs come back, at least in math and maybe elsewhere. Defining "functioning" isn't trivial, but it isn't impossible either. If the mind has something like desires, then a functioning mind is one which tends to get its desires more often than if it didn't desire them.
If you cleave mindspace at the joints, you find sections for which there are UCAs. I don't immediately see how to get anything interesting about morality that way, but it's an avenue worth pursuing.
This is a helpful clarification. "No universally compelling arguments" is a poor standard for determining whether something is objective, as it is trivial to describe an agent that is compelled by no arguments. But I think people here use it as tag for a different argument: that it's totally unclear how a Bayesian reasoner ought to update moral beliefs, and that such a thing doesn't even seem like a meaningful enterprise. They're 'beliefs' that don't pay rent.. It's one of those things where the title is used so much it's meaning has become divorced from the content.
I agree with the message, but I'm not sure whether I think things with a binomial monkey prior, or an anti-inductive prior, or that don't implement (a dynamic like) modus ponens on some level even if they don't do anything interesting with verbalized logical propositions, deserve to be called "minds".
General comment (which has shown up many times in the comments on this issue): taboo "mind", and this conversation seems clearer. It's obvious that not all physical processes are altered by logical arguments, and any 'mind' is going to be implemented as a physical process in a reductionist universe.
Specific comment: This old comment by PhilGoetz seems relevant, and seems similar to contemporary comments by TheAncientGeek. If you view 'mind' as a subset of 'optimization process', in that they try to squeeze the future into a particular region, the...
On this topic, I once wrote:
...I used to be frustrated and annoyed by what I thought was short-sightedness and irrationality on the behalf of people. But as I've learned more of the science of rationality, I've become far more understanding.
People having strong opinions on things they know nothing about? It doesn't show that they're stupid. It just shows that on issues of low personal relevance, it's often more useful to have opinions that are chosen to align with the opinions of those you wish to associate yourself with, and that this has been true so ofte
That was well expressed, in a way, but seems to me to miss the central point. People who dthink there are universally compelling arguments in science or maths, don't mean the same thing by "universal". They don't think their universally compelling arguments would work on crazy people, and don't need to be told they wouldn't work on crazy AI's or pocket calculators either. They are just not including those in the set "universal".
ADDED:
It has been mooted that NUCA is intended as a counterblast to Why Can't an AGI Work Out Its Own Morality...
Very good post. It is a very nice summation of the issues in the metaethics sequence.
I shall be linking people this in the future.
So you can have a mind that rejects modus ponens but does this matter? Is such a mind good for anything?
The "argument" that compels me about modus ponens and simple arithmetic is that they work with small real examples. You can implement super simple symbolic logic using pebbles and cups. You can prove modus ponens by truth tables, which could be implemented with pebbles and cups. So if arithmetic and simpler rules of logic map so clearly on to the real world, then these "truths" have an existence which is outside my own mind. Th...
Where Recursive Justification Hits Bottom and its comments should be linked for their discussion of anti-inductive priors.
(Edit: Oh, this is where the first quote in the post came from.)
Nitpicking: Modus ponens is not about "deriving". It's about B being true. (Your description matches the provability relation, the "|-" operator.) It's not clear how "fundamental" modus ponens it is. You can make up new logics without that connective and other exotic connectives (such as those in modal logics). Then, you'd ask yourself what to do with them... Speaking of relevance, even the standard connectives are not very useful by themselves. We get a lot of power from non-logical axioms, with a lot of handwaving about how ...
This is a bit long for the key point: 'Don't be bothered by a lack of universally compelling arguments against because human mind spaces contains enough minds that will not accept modus or even less.' which comes at the end. You risk TLDR if you don't put a summary at the top.
Otherwise I think the title does't really fit, or else I possibly just don't see how it derives the relation - rather the opposite: 'No Universally Compelling Arguments against Crackpots'.
Last week, I started a thread on the widespread sentiment that people don't understand the metaethics sequence. One of the things that surprised me most in the thread was this exchange:
Commenter: "I happen to (mostly) agree that there aren't universally compelling arguments, but I still wish there were. The metaethics sequence failed to talk me out of valuing this."
Me: "But you realize that Eliezer is arguing that there aren't universally compelling arguments in any domain, including mathematics or science? So if that doesn't threaten the objectivity of mathematics or science, why should that threaten the objectivity of morality?"
Commenter: "Waah? Of course there are universally compelling arguments in math and science."
Now, I realize this is just one commenter. But the most-upvoted comment in the thread also perceived "no universally compelling arguments" as a major source of confusion, suggesting that it was perceived as conflicting with morality not being arbitrary. And today, someone mentioned having "no universally compelling arguments" cited at them as a decisive refutation of moral realism.
After the exchange quoted above, I went back and read the original No Universally Compelling Arguments post, and realized that while it had been obvious to me when I read it that Eliezer meant it to apply to everything, math and science included, it was rather short on concrete examples, perhaps in violation of Eliezer's own advice. The concrete examples can be found in the sequences, though... just not in that particular post.
First, I recommend reading The Design Space of Minds-In-General if you haven't already. TLDR; the space of minds in general ginormous and includes some downright weird minds. The space of human minds is a teeny tiny dot in the larger space (in case this isn't clear, the diagram in that post isn't remotely drawn to scale). Now with that out of the way...
There are minds in the space of minds-in-general that do not recognize modus ponens.
Modus ponens is the rule of inference that says that if you have a statement of the form "If A then B", and also have "A", then you can derive "B". It's a fundamental part of logic. But there are possible mind that reject it. A brilliant illustration of this point can be found in Lewis Carroll's dialog "What the Tortoise Said to Achilles" (for those not in the know, Carroll was a mathematician; Alice in Wonderland is secretly full of math jokes).
Eliezer covers the dialog in his post Created Already In Motion, but here's the short version: In Carroll's dialog, the tortoise asks Achilles to imagine someone rejecting a particular instance of modus ponens (drawn from Euclid's Elements, though that isn't important). The Tortoise suggests that such a person might be persuaded by adding an additional premise, and Achilles goes along with it—foolishly, because this quickly leads to an infinite regress when the Tortoise suggests that someone might reject the new argument in spite of accepting the premises (which leads to another round of trying to patch the argument, and then..)
"What the Tortoise Said to Achilles" is one of the reasons I tend to think of the so-called "problem of induction" as a pseudo-problem. The "problem of induction" is often defined as the problem of how to justify induction, but it seems to make just as much senses to ask how to justify deduction. But speaking of induction...
There are minds in the space of minds-in-general that reason counter-inductively.
To quote Eliezer:
If this bothers you, well, I refer you back to Lewis' Carroll's dialog. There are also minds in the mind design space that ignore the standard laws of logic, and are furthermore totally unbothered by (what we would regard as) the absurdities produced by doing so. Oh, but if you thought that was bad, consider this...
There are minds in the space of minds-in-general that use a maximum entropy prior, and never learn anything.
Here's Eliezer again discussing a problem where you have to predict whether a ball drawn out of an urn will be red or white, based on the color of the balls that have been previously drawn out of the urn:
You may think, while minds such as I've been describing are possible in theory, they're unlikely to evolve anywhere in the universe, and probably they wouldn't survive long if programmed as an AI. And you'd probably be right about that. On the other hand, it's not hard to imagine minds that are generally able to get along well in the world, but irredeemably crazy on particular questions. Sometimes, it's tempting to suspect some humans of being this way, and even if that isn't literally true of any humans, it's not hard to imagine as just a more extreme form of existing human tendencies. See e.g. Robin Hanson on near vs. far mode, and imagine a mind that will literally never leave far mode on certain questions, regardless of the circumstances.
It used to disturb me to think that there might be, say, young earth creationists in the world who couldn't be persuaded to give up their young earth creationism by any evidence or arguments, no matter how long they lived. Yet I've realized that, while there may or may not be actual human young earth creationists like that (it's an empirical question), there are certainly possible minds in the space of mind designs like that. And when I think about that fact, I'm forced to shrug my shoulders and say, "oh well" and leave it at that.
That means I can understand why people would be bothered by a lack of universally compelling arguments for their moral views... but you shouldn't be any more bothered by that than by the lack of universally compelling arguments against young earth creationism. And if you don't think the lack of universally compelling arguments is a reason to think there's no objective truth about the age of the earth, you shouldn't think it's a reason to think there's no objective truth about morality.
(Note: this may end up being just the first in a series of posts on the metaethics sequence. People are welcome to discuss what I should cover in subsequent posts in the comments.)
Added: Based on initial comments, I wonder if some people who describe themselves as being bothered the lack of universally compelling arguments would more accurately describe themselves as being bothered by the orthogonality thesis.