The fixed point theorem of provability logic is a key result that gives a explicit procedure to find equivalences for sentences such as the ones produced by the diagonal lemma.
In its most simple formulation, it states that:
Let be a modal sentence modalized in . Then there exists a letterless such that [1].
This result can be generalized for cases in which letter sentences other than appear in the original formula, and the case where multiple formulas are present.
The that appears in the statement of the theorem is called a fixed point of on .
In general, a fixed point of a formula on will be a modal formula in which does not appear such that .
The fixed point theorem gives a sufficient condition for the existence of fixed points, namely that is modalized in . It is an open problem to determine a necessary condition for the existence of fixed points.
Fixed points satisfy some important properties:
If is a fixed point of on , then . This coincides with our intuition of what a fixed point is, since this can be seen as an argument that when fed to it returns something equivalent to itself.
Since is a fixed point, . Since is normal, it is closed under substitution. By substituing for , we find that .
But trivially , so .
and are fixed points of if and only if . This is knows as the uniqueness of fixed points.
Let be a fixed point on of ; that is, .
Suppose is such that . Then by the first substitution theorem, for every formula . If , then , from which it follows that .
Conversely, if and are fixed points, then , so since is closed under substitution, . Since , it follows that .
The special case of the fixed point theorem is what we stated at the beginning of the page. Namely:
Let be a modal sentence modalized in p. Then there exists a letterless such that .
There is a nice semantical procedure based on Kripke models that allows to compute as a truth functional compound of sentences [2]. (ie, is in normal form).
Let be a modal sentence modalized in in which no other sentence letter appears (we call such a sentence a -sentence). We want to calculate 's fixed point on . This procedure bears a resemblance to the trace method for evaluating letterless modal sentences.
We are going to introduce the notion of the -trace of a -sentence , notated by . The -trace maps modal sentences to sets of natural numbers, and is defined recursively as follows:
Lemma: Let be a finite, transitive and irreflexive Kripke model in which B$ a -sentence. Then iff .
Coming soon
Lemma: The -trace of a -sentence is either finite or cofinite, and furthermore either it has less than elements or lacks less than elements, where is the number of s in .
Coming soon
Those two lemmas allow us to express the truth value of in terms of world ranks for models in which is valid. Then the fixed point will be either the union or the negation of the union of a finite number of sentences [3]
In the following section we work through an example, and demonstrate how can we easily compute those fixed points using a Kripke chain.
For an example, we will compute the fixed point for the modal Gödel sentence and analyze its significance.
We start by examining the truth value of in the th rank worlds. Since the only letter is and it is modalized, this can be done without problem (remember that is always true in the rank worlds, no mater what is). Now we apply to the constraint of having the same truth value as .
We iterate the procedure for the next world ranks.
Since there is only one in the formula, the chain is guaranteed to stabilize in the first world and there is no need for going further. We have shown the truth values in world to show that this is indeed the case.
From the table we have just constructed it becomes evident that . Thus .
Therefore, . Thus, the fixed point for the modal Gödel sentence is the consistency of arithmetic!
By employing the arithmetical soundness of GL, we can translate this result to and show that for every sentence of arithmetic.
Since in we can construct by the diagonal lemma such that , by necessitation we have that for such a then . By the theorem we just proved using the fixed point, then . SInce everything proves is true then .
Surprisingly enough, the Gödel sentence is equivalent to the consistency of arithmetic! This makes more evident that is not provable unless is inconsistent, and that it is not disprovable unless it is -inconsistent.
Exercise: Find the fixed point for the Henkin sentence .
Thus the fixed point is simply .
The first generalization we make to the theorem is allowing the appearance of sentence letters other than the one we are fixing. The concrete statement is as follows:
Let be a modal sentence modalized in p. Then has a fixed point on .%%.
There are several constructive procedures for finding the fixed point in the general case.
One particularly simple procedure is based on k-decomposition.
Let be as in the hypothesis of the fixed point theorem. Then we can express as , since every occurs within the scope of a (The s are omitted for simplicity, but they may appear scattered between and the s). This is called a -decomposition of .
If is -decomposable, then it is already a fixed point, since does not appear.
Otherwise, consider , which is -decomposable.
Assuming that the procedure works for decomposable formulas, we can use it to compute a fixed point for each . Now, is the desired fixed point for .
This procedure constructs fixed points with structural similarity to the original sentence.
Let's compute the fixed point of .
We can 1-decompose the formula in , .
Then , which is its own fixed point. Thus the desired fixed point is .
Exercise: Compute the fixed point of .
One possible decomposition of the the formula at hand is , .
Now we compute the fixed point of , which is simply .
Therefore the fixed point of the whole expression is
Suppose that are modal sentences such that is modalized in (possibly containing sentence letters other than ).
Then there exists in which no appears such that .
We will prove it by induction.
For the base step, we know by the fixed point theorem that there is such that
Now suppose that for we have such that .
By the second substitution theorem, . Therefore we have that .
If we iterate the replacements, we finally end up with .
Again by the fixed point theorem, there is such that .
But as before, by the second substitution theorem, .
Let stand for , and by combining the previous lines we find that .
By Goldfarb's lemma, we do not need to check the other direction, so and the proof is finished
One remark: the proof is wholly constructive. You can iterate the construction of fixed point following the procedure implied by the construction of the to compute fixed points.
An immediate consequence of the theorem is that for those fixed points and every , .
Indeed, since is closed under substitution, we can make the change for in the theorem to get that .
Since the righthand side is trivially a theorem of , we get the desired result.