Related: http://lesswrong.com/lw/1kh/the_correct_contrarian_cluster/, http://lesswrong.com/lw/1mh/that_magical_click/, http://lesswrong.com/lw/18b/reason_as_memetic_immune_disorder/
Given a claim, and assuming that its truth or falsehood would be important to you, how do you decide if it's worth investigating? How do you identify "bunk" or "crackpot" ideas?
Here are some examples to give an idea.
"Here's a perpetual motion machine": bunk. "I've found an elementary proof of Fermat's Last Theorem": bunk. "9-11 was an inside job": bunk.
"Humans did not cause global warming": possibly bunk, but I'm not sure. "The Singularity will come within 100 years": possibly bunk, but I'm not sure. "The economic system is close to collapse": possibly bunk, but I'm not sure.
"There is a genetic difference in IQ between races": I think it's probably false, but not quite bunk. "Geoengineering would be effective in mitigating global warming": I think it's probably false, but not quite bunk.
(These are my own examples. They're meant to be illustrative, not definitive. I imagine that some people here will think "But that's obviously not bunk!" Sure, but you probably can think of some claim that *you* consider bunk.)
A few notes of clarification: I'm only examining factual, not normative, claims. I also am not looking at well established claims (say, special relativity) which are obviously not bunk. Neither am I looking at claims where it's easy to pull data that obviously refutes them. (For example, "There are 10 people in the US population.") I'm concerned with claims that look unlikely, but not impossible. Also, "Is this bunk?" is not the same question as "Is this true?" A hypothesis can turn out to be false without being bunk (for example, the claim that geological formations were created by gradual processes. That was a respectable position for 19th century geologists to take, and a claim worth investigating, even if subsequent evidence did show it to be false.) The question "Is this bunk?" arises when someone makes an unlikely-sounding claim, but I don't actually have the knowledge right now to effectively refute it, and I want to know if the claim is a legitimate subject of inquiry or the work of a conspiracy theory/hoax/cult/crackpot. In other words, is it a scientific or a pseudoscientific hypothesis? Or, in practical terms, is it worth it for me or anybody else to investigate it?
This is an important question, and especially to this community. People involved in artificial intelligence or the Singularity or existential risk are on the edge of the scientific mainstream and it's particularly crucial to distinguish an interesting hypothesis from a bunk one. Distinguishing an innovator from a crackpot is vital in fields where there are both innovators and crackpots.
I claim bunk exists. That is, there are claims so cracked that they aren't worth investigating. "I was abducted by aliens" has such a low prior that I'm not even going to go check up on the details -- I'm simply going to assume the alleged alien abductee is a fraud or nut. Free speech and scientific freedom do not require us to spend resources investigating every conceivable claim. Some claims are so likely to be nonsense that, given limited resources, we can justifiably dismiss them.
But how do we determine what's likely to be nonsense? "I know it when I see it" is a pretty bad guide.
First idea: check if the proposer uses the techniques of rationality and science. Does he support claims with evidence? Does he share data and invite others to reproduce his experiments? Are there internal inconsistencies and logical fallacies in his claim? Does he appeal to dogma or authority? If there are features in the hypothesis itself that mark it as pseudoscience, then it's safely dismissed; no need to look further.
But what if there aren't such clear warning signs? Our gracious host Eliezer Yudkowsky, for example, does not display those kinds of obvious tip-offs of pseudoscience -- he doesn't ask people to take things on faith, he's very alert to fallacies in reasoning, and so on. And yet he's making an extraordinary claim (the likelihood of the Singularity), a claim I do not have the background to evaluate, but a claim that seems implausible. What now? Is this bunk?
A key thing to consider is the role of the "mainstream." When a claim is out of the mainstream, are you justified in moving it closer to the bunk file? There are three camps I have in mind, who are outside the academic mainstream, but not obviously (to me) dismissed as bunk: global warming skeptics, Austrian economists, and singularitarians. As far as I can tell, the best representatives of these schools don't commit the kinds of fallacies and bad arguments of the typical pseudoscientist. How much should we be troubled, though, by the fact that most scientists of their disciplines shun them? Perhaps it's only reasonable to give some weight to that fact.
Or is it? If all the scientists themselves are simply making their judgments based on how mainstream the outsiders are, then "mainstream" status doesn't confer any information. The reason you listen to academic scientists is that you expect that at least some of them have investigated the claim themselves. We need some fraction of respected scientists -- even a small fraction -- who are crazy enough to engage even with potentially crackpot theories, if only to debunk them. But when they do that, don't they risk being considered crackpots themselves? This is some version of "Tolerate tolerance." If you refuse to trust anybody who even considers seriously a crackpot theory, then you lose the basis on which you reject that crackpot theory.
So the question "What is bunk?", that is, the question, "What is likely enough to be worth investigating?", apparently destroys itself. You can only tell if a claim is unlikely by doing a little investigation. It's probably a reflexive process: when you do a little investigation, if it's starting to look more and more like the claim is false, you can quit, but if it's the opposite, then the claim is probably worth even more investigation.
The thing is, we all have different thresholds for what captures our attention and motivates us to investigate further. Some people are willing to do a quick Google search when somebody makes an extraordinary claim; some won't bother; some will go even further and do extensive research. When we check the consensus to see if a claim is considered bunk, we're acting on the hope that somebody has a lower threshold for investigation than we do. We hope that some poor dogged sap has spent hours diligently refuting 9-11 truthers so that we don't have to. From an economic perspective, this is an enormous free-rider problem, though -- who wants to be that poor dogged sap? The hope is that somebody, somewhere, in the human population is always inquiring enough to do at least a little preliminary investigation. We should thank the poor dogged saps of the world. We should create more incentives to be a poor dogged sap. Because if we don't have enough of them, we're going to be very mistaken when we think "Well, this wasn't important enough for anyone to investigate, so it must be bunk."
(N.B. I am aware that many climate scientists are being "poor dogged saps" by communicating with and attempting to refute global warming skeptics. I'm not aware if there are economists who bother trying to refute Austrian economics, or if there are electrical engineers and computer scientists who spend time being Singularity skeptics.)
Sorry to take a while to look at this.
It would. I'm aware of what Dawkins has said about this - that one doesn't neeed to be an expert on fairies in order to conclude that they don't exist, and that this ought to apply to Gods as well. This is fair enough.
It's a rule of argument. If someone doesn't want to learn about fairies, that's their own concern. But if they want to persuade some other people who do believe in the fairies, they ought to take the time to learn enough about what those people say about fairies to plug into their world.
Theories are like languages, I think. If someone has a mental vocabulary which involves fairies, you will more easily persuade them if you can use the language too.
What too often happens is that a critic doesn't learn the other person's language. They then end up misrepresenting what the other party believes, and to follow that up, they tell them that their first step to knowledge is to throw away a language that they find useful in favour of a different one that they've never used. They then go on to make arguments to which they have no idea how I'm going to respond. As a persuasion strategy, this is a non-starter.
I'm not at all saying all theories/languages are equal, some are far better than others. But if you want to persuade an outsider, learning their language is only courteous, and gives you a huge advantage. You learn where the real problems of the other belief system are. You discover what it does successfully explain. You discover how to partially express your beliefs in their system, which makes it easier for them to accept and test what you're saying.
My original point is that, as an optimisation, you can immediately reject any arguer who hasn't realised that they need to talk the language of their hearers.
It does explain why Dawkin's book has resulted in more heat than light. Reading it, Dawkin's book can be summarised as saying "Your theism seems completely ridiculous, for all these reasons. I don't know how you believe it." The reply has more or less been "Yes, I can see that you don't know how we believe it. Perhaps if you did know that, you would have written a better book."
In the case of the theists, this is in fact quite difficult. I am actually a Christian myself so I can give you the inside track here. The formal 'arguments' that Christians put forward for believing in God actually have little to do with the real reasons that they do believe. Christians in particular are persuaded principally by the part of their mind that deals with relationships and morality - they believe God is so much more morally right than anything else they've heard about that only his existence explains the improvement. It's not based on the faculty of reason, though, it persuades through the interpersonal brain. Reason comes later, and actually maps quite poorly onto what the essence of their faith is for the most part. The outcome is what Dawkins observes - you can give those religious arguments a terrible intellectual thrashing, and it makes very little difference to what they believe afterwards. He's not really speaking their language.
Another example of this is the opposite phenomenon - Christians, speaking in their own language that doesn't connect to atheists, say they don't believe in atheism because it's immoral. If you can imagine how likely such an argument is to impress Richard Dawkins, you have perhaps a mirror image of why his argument doesn't impress the theists.
Trying to express yourself in the language of the other party makes a huge difference. Let's take as an example Max Tegmark's mathematical universe hypothesis - the ultimate ensemble theory. Suppose he's right about part of this - that everything that's mathematically rationally describable 'exists' - whatever that is. But suppose he's wrong about the other part - that this forms an ensemble. Suppose instead it forms a network - that everything that exists is actually a conceptual network of interconnected mathematical concepts - an ultimate network of ideas. Not inherently implausible - it certainly is about the simplest possible description of what might exist that I can think of.
It also is pretty much a description of an omniscient God. But if I'd just talked about that in my language, it wouldn't have been as interesting.
Atheism isn't really Dawkin's main focus either. Dawkins isn't primarily against God - he's against faith. He believes people ought to believe things for rational reasons, not because they ought to, or that they'll be saved eternally if they do. Where Dawkins is most readable is when he's talking about 'survival machines', or the way each individual gene in an organism is out to optimise its own survival in its own way - whether that's good for the organism / species or not. Rationality and reason are his first love - atheism is more of a consequence of this than a belief in its own right. I very much share his view that people ought to believe things for rational reasons. Dawkins knows what systemic understanding is - I find the creationists assertion that there is no such thing - both in their arguments for rejecting science and in their own woeful lack of a systemic alternative view - very disturbing. I'd rather read Dawkins any day.
Why is this a good optimization? Do you have any particular evidence that an arguer who is willing to learn and use your language is more likely to have accurate beliefs?