Edge.org has recently been discussing "the myth of AI". Unfortunately, although Superintelligence is cited in the opening, most of the participants don't seem to have looked into Bostrom's arguments. (Luke has written a brief response to some of the misunderstandings Pinker and others exhibit.) The most interesting comment is Stuart Russell's, at the very bottom:
Of Myths and Moonshine
"We switched everything off and went home. That night, there was very little doubt in my mind that the world was headed for grief."
So wrote Leo Szilard, describing the events of March 3, 1939, when he demonstrated a neutron-induced uranium fission reaction. According to the historian Richard Rhodes, Szilard had the idea for a neutron-induced chain reaction on September 12, 1933, while crossing the road next to Russell Square in London. The previous day, Ernest Rutherford, a world authority on radioactivity, had given a "warning…to those who seek a source of power in the transmutation of atoms – such expectations are the merest moonshine."
Thus, the gap between authoritative statements of technological impossibility and the "miracle of understanding" (to borrow a phrase from Nathan Myhrvold) that renders the impossible possible may sometimes be measured not in centuries, as Rod Brooks suggests, but in hours.
None of this proves that AI, or gray goo, or strangelets, will be the end of the world. But there is no need for a proof, just a convincing argument pointing to a more-than-infinitesimal possibility. There have been many unconvincing arguments – especially those involving blunt applications of Moore's law or the spontaneous emergence of consciousness and evil intent. Many of the contributors to this conversation seem to be responding to those arguments and ignoring the more substantial arguments proposed by Omohundro, Bostrom, and others.
The primary concern is not spooky emergent consciousness but simply the ability to make high-quality decisions. Here, quality refers to the expected outcome utility of actions taken, where the utility function is, presumably, specified by the human designer. Now we have a problem:
1. The utility function may not be perfectly aligned with the values of the human race, which are (at best) very difficult to pin down.
2. Any sufficiently capable intelligent system will prefer to ensure its own continued existence and to acquire physical and computational resources – not for their own sake, but to succeed in its assigned task.
A system that is optimizing a function of n variables, where the objective depends on a subset of size k<n, will often set the remaining unconstrained variables to extreme values; if one of those unconstrained variables is actually something we care about, the solution found may be highly undesirable. This is essentially the old story of the genie in the lamp, or the sorcerer's apprentice, or King Midas: you get exactly what you ask for, not what you want. A highly capable decision maker – especially one connected through the Internet to all the world's information and billions of screens and most of our infrastructure – can have an irreversible impact on humanity.
This is not a minor difficulty. Improving decision quality, irrespective of the utility function chosen, has been the goal of AI research – the mainstream goal on which we now spend billions per year, not the secret plot of some lone evil genius. AI research has been accelerating rapidly as pieces of the conceptual framework fall into place, the building blocks gain in size and strength, and commercial investment outstrips academic research activity. Senior AI researchers express noticeably more optimism about the field's prospects than was the case even a few years ago, and correspondingly greater concern about the potential risks.
No one in the field is calling for regulation of basic research; given the potential benefits of AI for humanity, that seems both infeasible and misdirected. The right response seems to be to change the goals of the field itself; instead of pure intelligence, we need to build intelligence that is provably aligned with human values. For practical reasons, we will need to solve the value alignment problem even for relatively unintelligent AI systems that operate in the human environment. There is cause for optimism, if we understand that this issue is an intrinsic part of AI, much as containment is an intrinsic part of modern nuclear fusion research. The world need not be headed for grief.
I'd quibble with a point or two, but this strikes me as an extraordinarily good introduction to the issue. I hope it gets reposted somewhere it can stand on its own.
Russell has previously written on this topic in Artificial Intelligence: A Modern Approach and the essays "The long-term future of AI," "Transcending complacency on superintelligent machines," and "An AI researcher enjoys watching his own execution." He's also been interviewed by GiveWell.
Calling it a utility function does not make it a utility function. A utility function maps decisions to utilities, in an entity which decides among its available choices by evaluating that function for each one and making the decision that maximises the value. Or as Wikipedia puts it, in what seems a perfectly sensible summary definition covering all its more detailed uses, utility is "the (perceived) ability of something to satisfy needs or wants." That is the definition of utility and utility functions; that is what everyone means by them. It makes no sense to call something completely different by the same name in order to preserve the truth of the sentence "humans have utility functions". The sentence has remained the same but the proposition it expresses has been changed, and changed into an uninteresting tautology. The original proposition expressed by "humans have utility functions" is still false, or if one is going to argue that it is true, it must be done by showing that humans have utility functions in the generally understood meaning of the term.
No, it should not; it cannot. Behaviour depends not only on current stimuli but the human's entire past history, internal and external. Unless you are going to redefine "stimuli" to mean "entire past light-cone" (which of course the word does not mean) this does not work. Furthermore, that entire past history is also causally influenced by the human's behaviour. Such cyclic patterns of interaction cannot be understood as functions from stimulus to response.
In order to arrive at this subjectively ineluctable ("meh, unless there's uncomputable magic") statement, you have redefined the key words to make them mean what no-one ever means by them. It's the Texas Sharpshooter Utility Function fallacy yet again: look at what the organism does, then label that as having higher "utility" than the things it did not do.
I appreciate your point.
Mostly, I'm concerned that "strictly speaking, humans don't have VNM-utility functions, so that's that, full stop" can be interpreted like a stop sign, when in fact humans do have preferences (clearly) and do tend to choose actions to try to satisfice those preferences at least part of the time. To the extent that we'd deny that, we'd deny the existence of any kind of "agent" instantiated in the physical universe. There is predictable behavior for the most part, which can be modelled. And anything that can be co... (read more)