In the standard approach to axiomatic Bayesian decision theory, an agent (a decision maker) doesn't prefer Act #1 to Act #2 because the expected utility of Act #1 exceeds that of Act #2. Instead, the agent states its preferences over a set of risky acts, and if these stated preferences are consistent with a certain set of axioms (e.g. the VNM axioms, or the Savage axioms), it can be proven that the agent's decisions can be described as if the agent were assigning probabilities and utilities to outcomes and then maximizing expected utility. (Let's call this the ex post approach.)
Peterson (2004) introduces a different approach, which he calls the ex ante approach. In many ways, this approach is more intuitive. The agent assigns probabilities and utilities directly to outcomes (not acts), and these assignments are used to generate preferences over acts. Using this approach, Peterson claims to have shown that the principle of expected utility maximization can be derived from just four axioms.
As Peterson (2009:75,77) explains:
The aim of the axiomatization [in the ex ante approach] is to show that the utility of an act equals the expected utility of its outcomes.
...The axioms... entail that the utility of an act equals the expected utility of its outcomes. Or, put in slightly different words, the act that has the highest utility (is most attractive) will also have the highest expected utility, and vice versa. This appears to be a strong reason for letting the expected utility principle guide one's choices in decision under risk.
Jensen (2012:428) calls the ex ante approach "controversial," but I can't find any actual published rebuttals to Peterson (2004), so maybe Jensen just means that Peterson's result is "new and not yet percolated to the broad community."
Peterson (2008) explores the ex ante approach in more detail, under the unfortunate title of "non-Bayesian decision theory." (No, Peterson doesn't reject Bayesianism.) Cozic (2011) is a review of Peterson (2008) that may offer the quickest entry point into the subject of ex ante axiomatic decision theory.
Peterson (2009:210) illustrates the controversy nicely:
...even if [this] discussion may appear a bit theoretical... the controversy over [ex post and ex ante approaches] is likely to have important practical implications. For example, a forty-year-old woman seeking advice about whether to, say, divorce her husband, is likely to get very different answers from the [two approaches]. The [ex post approach] will advise the woman to first figure out what her preferences are over a very large set of risky acts, including the one she is thinking about performing, and then just make sure that all preferences are consistent with certain structural requirements. Then, as long as none of the structural requirements is violated, the woman is free to do whatever she likes, no matter what her beliefs and desires actually are... The [ex ante approach] will [instead] advise the woman to first assign numerical utilities and probabilities to her desires and beliefs, and then aggregate them into a decision by applying the principle of maximizing expected utility.
I'm not a decision theory expert, so I'd be very curious to hear what LW's decision theorists think of the axiomatization in Peterson (2004) — whether it works, and how significant it is.
A utility function that accurately reflects the beliefs and values of the human it's designed for. Someone looking for guidance would get assistance in discovering what their beliefs and values about the situation are, rather than just math help and a consistency check. Similarly, someone could accidentally write a utility function that drowns them in vinegar, and it would be nice if the decision-making apparatus noticed and didn't.
That's my interpretation of "he's just saying that it would also be nice to have a decision theory that can tell you what you should choose given what you believe and what you value."
This looks like it boils down to "the utility of an act is the weighted sum of the utility of its consequences." It's not clear to me what good formulating it like that does, and I don't like that axiom 4 from the 2009 version looks circular. (You're allowed to adjust the utility of different equiprobable outcomes so long as the total utility of the act is preserved. But, uh, aren't we trying to prove that we can calculate the utility of an act with multiple possible outcome utilities, and haven't we only assumed that it works for acts with only one possible outcome utility?)
Was Thm 4.1 an example of a useful result?