This post will just be a concrete math question. I am interested in this question because I have recently come tor reject the independence axiom of VNM, and am thus playing with some weaker versions.
Let be a finite set of deterministic outcomes. Let be the space of all lotteries over these outcomes, and let be a relation on . We write if A B and B A. We write if but not .
Here are some axioms we can assume about :
A1. For all , either or (or both).
A2. For all , if , and , then .
A3. For all , if , and , then there exists a such that .
A4. For all , and if , then .
A5. For all , and , if and , then .
Here is one bonus axiom:
B1. For all , and , if and only if .
(Note that B1 is stronger than both A4 and A5)
Finally, here are some conclusions of successively increasing strength:
C1. There exists a function such that if and only if .
C2. Further, we require is quasi-concave.
C3. Further, we require is continuous.
C4. Further, we require is concave.
C5. Further, we require is linear.
The standard VNM utility theorem can be thought of as saying A1, A2, A3, and B1 together imply C5.
Here is the main question I am curious about:
Q1: Do A1, A2, A3, A4, and A5 together imply C4? [ANSWER: NO]
(If no, how can we salvage C4, by adding or changing some axioms?)
Here are some sub-questions that would constitute significant partial progress, and that I think are interesting in their own right:
Q2: Do A1, A2, A3, and A4 together imply C3? [ANSWER: NO]
Q3: Do C3 and A5 together imply C4? [ANSWER: NO]
(Feel free to give answers that are only partial progress, and use this space to think out loud or discuss anything else related to weaker versions of VNM.)
EDIT:
AlexMennen actually resolved the question in the negative as stated, but my curiosity is not resolved, since his argument is violating continuity, and I really care about concavity. My updated main question is now:
Q4: Do A1, A2, A3, A4, and A5 together imply that there exists a concave function such that if and only if ? [ANSWER: NO]
(i.e. We do not require to be continuous.)
This modification also implies interest in the subquestion:
Q5: Do A1, A2, A3, and A4 together imply C2?
EDIT 2:
Here is another bonus axiom:
B2. For all , if , then there exists some such that .
(Really, we don't need to assume is already in . We just need it to be possible to add a , and extend our preferences in a way that satisfies the other axioms, and A3 will imply that such a lottery was already in . We might want to replace this with a cleaner axiom later.)
Q6: Do A1, A2, A3, A5, and B2 together imply C4? [ANSWER: NO]
EDIT 3:
We now have negative answers to everything other than Q5, which I still think is pretty interesting. We could also weaken Q5 to include other axioms, like A5 and B2. Weakening the conclusion doesn't help, since it is easy to get C2 from C1 and A4.
I would still really like some axioms that get us all the way to a concave function, but I doubt there will be any simple ones. Concavity feels like it really needs more structure that does not translate well to a preference relation.
Q5 is true if (as you assumed), the space of lotteries is the space of distributions over a finite set. (For a general convex set, you can get long-line phenomena.)
First, without proof, I'll state the following generalization.
Theorem 1. Let ⪯ be a relation on a convex space L satisfying axioms A1, A2, A3, and the following additional continuity axiom. For all A,B1,B2,C∈L, the set
{p∈[0,1]∣A≺pB1+(1−p)B2≺C}is open in [0,1]. Then, there exists a function u from L to the long line such that u(A)≤u(B) iff A⪯B.
The proof is not too different, but simpler, if we also assume A4. In particular, we no longer need the extra continuity axiom, and we get a stronger conclusion. Nate sketched part of the proof of this already, but I want to be clearer about what is stated and skip fewer steps. In particular, I'm not sure how Nate's hypotheses rule out examples that require long-line-valued functions—maybe he's assuming that the domain of the preference relation is a finite-dimensional simplex like I am, but none of his arguments use this explicitly.
Theorem 2. Let ⪯ be a relation on a finite-dimensional simplex L=ΔΩ satisfying axioms A1-A4. Then, there is a quasiconcave function u:L→R such that u(A)≤u(B) iff A⪯B.
First, I'll set up some definitions and a lemma. For any lotteries A, B, let [A,B] denote the line segment
{pA+(1−p)B∣p∈[0,1]}.We say that preferences are increasing along a line segment [A,B] if whenever p≤q, we have
(1−p)A+pB⪯(1−q)A+qB.We will also use open and half-open interval notation in the corresponding way.
Lemma. Let ⪯ be a preference relation on a finite-dimensional simplex L=ΔΩ satisfying axioms A1-A4. Then, there are ⪯-minimal and -maximal elements in L.
Proof. First, we show that there is a minimal element. Axiom A4 states that for any mixture C=pA+(1−p)B, either C⪰A or C⪰B. By induction, it follows more generally that any convex combination C of finitely many elements (Ai)i∈I satisfies C⪰Ai for some i∈I. But every element is a convex combination of the vertices of L, so some vertex of L is ⪯-minimal.
The proof that there is a maximal element is more complex. Consider the family of sets
F={{B∈L∣B⪰A}∣A∈L}.This is a prefilter, so since L is compact (L here carries the Euclidean metric), it has a cluster point B. Either B will be a maximal element, or we will find some other maximal element. In particular, take any A∈L. We are done if A is a maximal element; otherwise, pick A′≻A. By the construction of F, for every n∈N, we can pick some Cn⪰A′ within a distance of 1n from B. Now, if we show that B itself satisfies B⪰A, it will follow that B is maximal.
The idea is to pass from our sequence (Cn)n∈N, with limit B, to another sequence lying on a line segment with endpoint B. We can use axiom A4, which is a kind of convexity, to control the preference relation on convex combinations of our points Cn, so these are the points that we will construct along a line segment. Once we have this line segment, we can finish by using A3, which is a kind of continuity restricted to line segments, to control B itself.
Let S⊆L be the set of lotteries in the affine span of the set {Cn}n∈N. Then, if we take some index set I⊆N such that (Cn)n∈I is a maximal affinely independent tuple, it follows that {Cn}n∈I affinely generates S. Hence, the convex combination
D=∑n∈I1|I|Cn,i.e. the barycenter of the simplex with vertices at (Cn)n∈I, is in the interior of the convex hull of {Cn}n∈I relative to S, so we can pick some r>0 such that the r-ball around D relative to S is contained in this simplex.
Now, we will see that every lottery E in the set (B,D] satisfies E⪰A′. For any ε>0, pick k so that Ck is in the ε-ball around B. Since the tangent vector v=B−Ck has length less than ε, the lottery
F=D+rε(B−Ck)is in the r-ball around D, and it is in S, so it is in the simplex with vertices (Cn)n∈I. Then, F⪰A′ by A4, and Ck⪰A′ by hypothesis. So, applying A4 again,
A′⪯rr+εCk+εr+εF=rr+εB+εr+εD.Using A4 one more time, it follows that every lottery
E∈[rr+εB+εr+εD,D]satisfies E⪰A′, and hence every lottery E∈(B,D].
Now we can finish up. If B≺A then, using A3 and the fact that D⪰A′≻A, there would have to be some lottery in [B,D] that is ⪯-equivalent to A, but this would contradict what we just concluded. So, B⪰A, and so B is ⪯-maximal. □
Proof of Theorem 2. Let C be a ⪯-minimal and D a ⪯-maximal element of L. First, we will see that preferences are increasing on [C,D], and then we will use this fact to construct a function L→R and show that it has the desired properties. Suppose preferences we not increasing; then, there would be A,B∈[C,D] such that A is closer to C while B is closer to D, and A≻B. Then, B would be a convex combination of A and D, but B≺A⪯D by the maximality of D, contradicting A4.
Now we can construct our utility function u:L→R using A3; for each ∼-class [A], we have C⪯A⪯D, so there is some[1] p∈[0,1] such that
(1−p)C+pD∼A.Then, let u(A′)=p for all A′∈[A]. Since preferences are increasing on [C,D], it is immediate that if u(A)≤u(B), then A⪯B. Conversely, if A⪯B, we have two cases. If A≺B, then B⋠A, so u(B)≰u(A), and so u(A)≤u(B). Finally, if A∼B, then u(A)=u(B) by construction.
Finally, since for all A,B∈L we have u(A)≤u(B) iff A⪯B, it follows immediately that u is quasiconcave by A4. □
Nate mentions using choice in his answer, but here at least the use of choice is removable. Since ⪯ is monotone on [C,D], the intersection of the ∼-class [A] with [C,D] is a subinterval of [C,D], so we can pick p based on the midpoint of that interval