Conservation of Expected Evidence

Conservation of Expected Evidence is a consequence of probability theory which states that for every expectation of evidence, there is an equal and opposite expectation of counterevidencecounter-evidence [1]. Conservation of Expected Evidence is about both the direction of the update and its magnitude: a low probability of seeing strong evidence in one direction must be balanced by a high probability of observing weak counterevidencecounter-evidence in the other direction [2]. The mere expectation of encountering evidence–before you've actually seen it–should not shift your prior beliefs. It also goes by other names, including the law of total expectation and the law of iterated expectations.

Consider a hypothesis H and evidence (observation) E. Prior probability of the hypothesis is P(H); posterior probability is either P(H|E) or P(H|¬E), depending on whether you observe E or not-E (evidence or counterevidence)counter-evidence). The probability of observing E is P(E), and probability of observing not-E is P(¬E). Thus, expected value of the posterior probability of the hypothesis is:

P(H|E)P(E)+P(H|¬E)P(¬E)

P(H)=P(H,E)+P(H,¬E) =P(H|E)P(E)+P(H|¬E)P(¬E)

D1=P(H|E)P(H).

D2=P(H|¬E)P(H).

Expectation of the change given positive evidence is equal to negated expectation of the change given counterevidence:counter-evidence:

D1P(E)=D2P(¬E).

P(H)=P(H,E)+P(H,¬E) =P(H|E)P(E)+P(H|¬E)P(¬E)

If you can anticipate in advance updating your belief in a particular direction, then you should just go ahead and update now. Once you know your destination, you are already there. 

In other way, if you expect the probability of a hypothesis to change as a result of observing some evidence, the amount of this change if the evidence is positive is:is

D1 = P(H|E) − P(H).

If the evidence is negative, the change is:is

\(D_{2}D2 = P(H|\neg{E}P(HE)-P(H)\\ − P(H).

D1 ⋅ P(E) =  − D2 ⋅ PE).

Conservation of Expected Evidence is a consequence of probability theory which states that for every expectation of evidence, there is an equal and opposite expectation of counterevidence.counterevidence [1]. Conservation of Expected Evidence is about botboth the direction of the update,update and its magnitude -magnitude: a low probability of seeing strong evidence in one direction must be balanced by a high probability of observing weak counterevidence in the other direction[direction [2]. The mere expectation of encountering evidence–before you've actually seen it–should not shift your prior beliefs. It also goes by other names, including the law of total expectation and the law of iterated expectations.

Conservation of Expected Evidence is a consequence of probability theory which states that for every expectation of evidence, there is an equal and opposite expectation of counterevidence. [1] Conservation of Expected Evidence is about bot the direction of the update, and its magnitude - a low probability of seeing strong evidence in one direction must be balanced by a high probability of observing weak counterevidence in the other direction[2]. The mere expectation of encountering evidence–before you've actually seen it–should not shift your prior beliefs. It also goes by other names, including the law of total expectation and the law of iterated expectations.

If you can anticipate in advance updating your belief in a particular direction, then you should just go ahead and update now. Once you know your destination, you are already there. On pain of paradox, a low probability of seeing strong evidence in one direction must be balanced by a high probability of observing weak counterevidence in the other direction.

Conservation of Expected Evidence is a consequence of probability theory which states that for every expectation of evidence, there is an equal and opposite expectation of counterevidence. [1] The mere expectation of encountering evidence–before you've actually seen it–should not shift your prior beliefs. It also goes by other names, including the law of total expectation and the law of iterated expectations.

From Conservation of Expected Evidence:

If you expect a strong probability of seeing weak evidence in one direction, it must be balanced by a weak expectation of seeing strong evidence in the other direction. If you’re very confident in your theory, and therefore anticipate seeing an outcome that matches your hypothesis, this can only provide a very small increment to your belief (it is already close to 1); but the unexpected failure of your prediction would (and must) deal your confidence a huge blow. On average, you must expect to be exactly as confident as when you started out. Equivalently, the mere expectation of encountering evidence—before you’ve actually seen it—should not shift your prior beliefs.If you expect a strong probability of seeing weak evidence in one direction, it must be balanced by a weak expectation of seeing strong evidence in the other direction. If you’re very confident in your theory, and therefore anticipate seeing an outcome that matches your hypothesis, this can only provide a very small increment to your belief (it is already close to 1); but the unexpected failure of your prediction would (and must) deal your confidence a huge blow. On average, you must expect to be exactly as confident as when you started out. Equivalently, the mere expectation of encountering evidence—before you’ve actually seen it—should not shift your prior beliefs.

These principlesConsider a hypothesis H and evidence (observation) E. Priorprobability of the hypothesis is P(H); posterior probability is either P(H|E) or P(H|¬E), depending on whether you observe E or not-E (evidence or counterevidence). The probability of observing E is P(E), and probability of observing not-E is P(¬E). Thus, expected value of the posterior probability of the hypothesis is:

P(H|E) ⋅ P(E) + P(HE) ⋅ PE)

But the prior probability of the hypothesis itself can be proven within standardtrivially broken up the same way:

P(H)=P(H,E)+P(H,¬E)=P(H|E)P(E)+P(H|¬E)P(¬E)

Thus, expectation of posterior probability theory. From Absence of Evidence is Evidence of Absence:equal to the prior probability.

But in probability theory, absence of evidence is always evidence of absence. If E is a binary event and P(H | E) > P(H), i.e., seeing E increasesIn other way, if you expect the probability of H,a hypothesis to change as a result of observing some evidence, the amount of this change if the evidence is positive is:

D1 = P(H|E) − P(H) 

If the evidence is negative, the change is:

\(D_{2} = P(H|\neg{E})-P(H)\\)

Expectation of the change given positive evidence is equal to negated expectation of the change given counterevidence:

D1 ⋅ P(E) =  − D2 ⋅ PE)

If you can anticipate in advance updating your belief in a particular direction, then P(H | ¬ E) < P(H), i.e., failure to observe E decreases theyou should just go ahead and update now. Once you know your destination, you are already there. On pain of paradox, a low probability of H . Theseeing strong evidence in one direction must be balanced by a high probability P(H) is a weighted mix of P(H | E) and P(H | ¬ E), and necessarily lies betweenobserving weak counterevidence in the two.other direction.

Notable Posts

  • Mistakes with Conservation of Expected Evidence
  • See Also

    Ruby20

    From the old discussion page:

    Talk:Conservation of expected evidence

    Regarding tilde versus overbar: I noticed that the Bayes' theorem page uses \neg, resulting in an ¬ character, for that purpose. Should we use that here (including in the inline plain-text renderings) for consistency? (We should probably standardize on one such character to signify negation on all wiki pages, whether ~ or ¬.) —Adam Atlas 17:12, 25 August 2010 (UTC)

    \neg it is, given that it seems to be more standard, and latex here renders tilde with inelegant amount of spacing around it. --Vladimir Nesov 20:41, 25 August 2010 (UTC)