Dmitry Vaintrob

Wiki Contributions

Comments

Sorted by
Answer by Dmitry Vaintrob70

The "History of Philosophy Without any Gaps" podcast (https://historyofphilosophy.net/) has for a while been alternating between weeks of Western and non-Western philosophy (which it does in a bit less detail, but still pretty in-depth). It's so far finished a series each on Indian and Africana philosophy and is currently starting on Ancient Chinese philosophy.

Insofar as you're thinking of evolution as analogous to gradient flow, it only makes sense if it's local and individual-level I think -- it is a category error to say that a species that has more members is a winner. The first shark that started eating its siblings in utero improved its genetic fitness (defined as the expected number of offspring in the specific environment it existed in) but might have harmed the survivability of the species as a whole.

It's neat to remember stories like this, but I want to note that this shouldn't necessarily update scientists to criticize novel work less. If an immune system doesn't sometimes overreact, it's not doing its job right, and for every story like this there are multiple other stories of genuinely false exciting-sounding ideas that got shut down by experts (for instance I learned about Schekhtman from the Constant podcast, where his story was juxtaposed with that of genuine quacks). Looking back at my experience of excited claims that were generally dismissed by more skeptical experts in fields I was following, the majority of them (for instance the superluminal neutrino, the room-temperature superconductor, various hype about potentially proving the Riemann hypothesis by well-established mathematicians) have been false.

I think there is a separate phenomenon (which was the explanation for the study about funerals), that older high-status scientists in funding-hungry fields will often continue to get funding and set priorities after they have stopped working on genuinely exciting stuff -- whether because of age, because of age-related conservatism bias, or simply because their area of expertise has become too well-developed to generate new ideas. In my experience in math and physics, from inside the field, this phenomenon generally does not look like a consensus that only the established people know what's going on (as in most of the stories here), but either conversely a quiet consensus that so-and-so famous person is starting to go crazy, or alternatively the normal disagreement between more conservative and more innovation-minded people about the value of a new idea. For example the most exciting development in my professional life as a mathematician was Jacob Lurie's development of "higher category theory", a revolution that allowed algebraists to seamlessly use tools from topology. There were many haters of this theory (many very young), but there was enough of a diffuse understanding that this is exciting and potentially revolutionary that his ideas did percolate and end up converting many of the haters (similarly with Grothendieck and schemes). Note that here I think math avoids the worst aspects of these dynamics because it doesn't require funding and is less competitive.

The upshot here is that I think it's valuable to try to resolve the issue of good ideas being shot down by traditionalists, but the solution might not be to "adopt lower standards for criticizing new / surprising ideas" but rather something more like pulling the rope sideways and looking for better standards that do better at separating promising innovation from hype.

Yes - I generally agree with this. I also realized that "interp score" is ambiguous (and the true end-to-end interp score is negligible, I agree), but what's more clearly true is that SAE features tend to be more interpretable. This might be largely explained by "people tend to think of interpretable features as branches of a decision tree, which are sparsely activating". But also like it was surprising to me that the top SAE features are significantly more interpretable than top PCA features

So to elaborate: we get significantly more interpretable features if we enforce sparsity than if we just do more standard clustering procedures. This is nontrivial! Of course this might be saying more about our notions of "interpretable feature" and how we parse semantics; but I can certainly imagine a world where PCA gives much better results, and would have in fact by default expected this to be true for the "most important" features even if I believed in superposition.

So I'm somewhat comfortable saying that the fact that imposing sparsity works so well is telling us something. I don't expect this to give "truly atomic" features from the network's PoV (any more than understanding Newtonian physics tells us about the standard model), but this seems like nontrivial progress to me.

I basically agree with you. But I think we have some nontrivial information, given enough caveats.

I think there are four hypotheses:

  • 1a. Neurons do >1 thing (neuron polysemanticity)
  • 1b. Insofar as we can find interesting atomic semantic features, they have >1 neuron (feature polysemanticity)
  • 2a. Features are sparse, i.e., (insofar as there exist interesting atomic semantic features), most have significantly <1/2 probability of being "on" for any input
  • 2b. Features are superpositional, i.e., (insofar as there exist interesting atomic semantic features), there are significantly more than dimension-many of them at any layer.

I think 1a/b and 2a/b are different in subtle ways, but most people would agree that in a rough directional yes/no sense, 1a<=>1b and 2a<=>2b (note that 2a=>2b requires some caveats -- but at the limit of lots of training in a complex problem with #training examples >= #parameters, if you have sparsity of features, it simply is inefficient to not have some form of superposition). I also agree that 1a/1b are a natural thing to posit a priori, and in fact it's much more surprising to me as someone coming from math that the "1 neuron:1 feature" hypothesis has any directional validity at all (i.e., sometimes interesting features are quite sparse in the neuron basis), rather than that anything that looks like a linear feature is polysemantic.

Now to caveat my statement: I don't think that neural nets are fully explained by a bunch of linear features, much less by a bunch of linear features in superposition. In fact, I'm not even close to100% on superposition existing at all in any truly "atomic" decomposition of computation. But at the same time we can clearly find semantic features which have explanatory power (in the same way that we can find pathways in biology, even if they don't correspond to any structures on the fundamental, in this case cellular, level).

And when I say that "interesting semantic features exist in superposition", what I really mean is that we have evidence for hypothesis 2a [edited, originally said 2b, which is a typo]. Namely, when we're looking for unsupervised ways to get such features, it turns out that enforcing sparsity (and doing an SAE) gives better interp scores than doing PCA. I think this is pretty strong evidence!

Thank you for the great response, and the (undeserved) praise of my criticism. I think it's really good that you're embracing the slightly unorthodox positions of sticking to ambitious convictions and acknowledging that this is unorthodox. I also really like your (a)-(d) (and agree that many of the adherents of the fields you list would benefit from similar lines of thinking).

I think we largely agree, and much of our disagreement probably boils down to where we draw the boundary between “mechanistic interpretability” and “other”. In particular, I fully agree with the first zoom level in your post, and with the causal structure of much of the rest of the diagram -- in particular, I like your notions of alignment robustness and mechanism distinction (the latter of which I think is original to ARC) and I think they may be central in a good alignment scenario. I also think that some notion of LPE should be present. I have some reservations about ELK as ARC envisions it (also of the “too much backchaining” variety), but think that the first-order insights there are valuable.

I think the core cruxes we have are:

  1. You write "Mechanistic interpretability has so far yielded very little in the way of beating baselines at downstream tasks". If I understand this correctly, you're saying it hasn't yet led to engineering improvements, either in capabilities or in "prosaic alignment" (at least compared to baselines like RLHF or "more compute").

    While I agree with this, I think that this isn't the right metric to apply. Indeed if you applied this metric, most science would not count as progress. Darwin wouldn’t get credit until his ideas got used to breed better crops and Einstein’s relativity would count as unproductive until the A-bomb (and the theory-application gap is much longer if you look at early advances in math and physics). Rather, I think that the question to ask is whether mechinterp (writ large, and in particular including a lot of people working in deep learning with no contact with safety) has made progress in understanding the internal functioning of AI or made nontrivially principled and falsifiable predictions about how it works. Here we would probably agree that the answer is pretty unambiguous. We have strong evidence that interesting semantic features exist in superposition (whether or not this is the way that the internal mechanisms use them). We understand the rough shape of some low-level circuits that do arithmetic and copying, and have rough ideas of the shapes of some high-level mechanisms (e.g. “function vectors”). To my eyes, this should count as progress in a very new science, and if I correctly understood your claim to be that you need to “beat black-box methods at useful tasks” to count as progress, I think this is too demanding.

  2. I think that I’m onboard with you on your desideratum #1 that theories should be “primarily mathematical” – in the sense that I think our tastes for rigor and principled theoretical science are largely aligned (and we both agree that we need good and somewhat fundamental theoretical principles to avoid misalignment). But math isn’t magic. In order to get a good mathematical tool for a real-world context, you need to make sure that you have correctly specified the context where it is to be applied, and more generally that you’ve found the “right formal context” for math. This makes me want to be careful about context before moving on to your insight #2 of trying to guess a specific information-theoretic criterion for how to formalize "an interpretation". Math is a dance, not a hammer: if a particular application of math isn’t working, it’s more likely that your context is wrong and you need to retarget and work outwards from simple examples, rather than try harder and route around contradictions. If you look at even a very mathy area of science, I would claim that most progress did not come from trying to make a very ambitious theoretical picture work and introducing epicycles in a “builder-breaker” fashion to get around roadblocks. For example if you look at the most mathematically heavy field that has applications in real life, this is QFT and SFT (which uses deep algebraic and topological insights and today is unquestionably useful in computer chips and the like). Its origin comes from physicists observing the idea of “universality” in some physical systems, and this leading Landau and others to work out that a special (though quite large and perturbation-invariant) class of statistical systems can be coarse-grained in a way that leads to these observed behaviors, and this led to ideas of renormalization, modern QFT and the like. If Landau’s generation instead tried to work really hard on mathematically analyzing general magnet-like systems without working up from applications and real-world systems, they’d end up in roughly the same place as Stephen Wolfram of trying to make overly ambitious claims about automata. The importance of looking for good theory-context fit is the main reason I would like to see more back-and-forth between more “boots-on-the-ground” interpretability theorists and more theoretical agendas like ARC and Agent Foundations. I’m optimistic that ARC’s mathematical agenda will eventually start iterating on carefully thinking about context and theory-context fit, but I think that some of the agenda I saw had the suboptimal, “use math as a hammer” shape. I might be misunderstanding here, and would welcome corrections.

  3. More specifically about “stories”, I agree with you that we are unlikely to be able to tell an easy-to-understand story about the internal working of AI’s (and in particular, I am very onboard with your first-level zoom of scalable alignment). I agree that the ultimate form of the thing we’re both gesturing at in the guise of “interpretability” will be some complicated, fractally recursive formalism using a language we probably don’t currently possess. But I think this is sort of true in a lot of other science. Better understanding leads to formulas, ideas and tools with a recursive complexity that humanity wouldn’t have guessed at before discovering them (again, QFT/SFT is an example). I’m not saying that this means “understanding AI will have the same type signature as QFT/ as another science”. But I am saying that the thing it will look like will be some complicated novel shape that isn’t either modern interp or any currently-accessible guess at its final form. And indeed, if it does turn out to take the shape of something that we can guess today – for example if heuristic arguments or SAEs turn out to be a shot in the right direction – I would guess that the best route towards discovering this is to build up a pluralistic collection of ideas that both iterate on creating more elegant/more principled mathematical ideas and iterate on understanding iteratively more interesting pieces of iteratively more general ML models in some class that expands from toy or real-world models. The history of math also does include examples of more "hammer"-like people: e.g. Wiles and Perelman, so making this bet isn't necessarily bad, and my criticism here should not be taken too prescriptively. In particular, I think your (a)-(d) are once again excellent guardrails against dangerous rabbitholes or communication gaps, and the only thing I can recommend somewhat confidently is to keep applicability to get interesting results about toy systems as a desideratum when building up the ambitious ideas.

Going a bit meta, I should flag an important intuition that we likely diverge on. I think that when some people defend using relatively formal math or philosophy to do alignment, they are going off of the following intuition:

  • if we restrict to real-world systems, we will be incorporating assumptions about the model class

  • if we assume these continue to hold for future systems by default, we are assuming some restrictive property remains true in complicated systems despite possible pressure to train against it to avoid detection, or more neutral pressures to learn new and more complex behaviors which break this property.

  • alternatively, if we try to impose this assumption externally, we will be restricting ourselves to a weaker, “understandable” class of algorithms that will be quickly outcompeted by more generic AI.

The thing I want to point out about this picture is that this models the assumption as closed. I.e., that it makes some exact requirement, like that some parameter is equal to zero. However, many of the most interesting assumptions in physics (including the one that made QFT go brrr, i.e., renormalizability) are open. I.e., they are some somewhat subtle assumptions that are perturbation-invariant and can’t be trained out (though they can be destroyed – in a clearly noticeable way – through new architectures or significant changes in complexity). In fact, there’s a core idea in physical theory, that I learned from some lecture notes of Ludvig Faddeev here, that you can trace through the development of physics as increasingly incorporating systems with more freedoms and introducing perturbations to a physical system starting with (essentially) classical fluid mechanics and tracing out through quantum mechanics -> QFT, but always making sure you’re considering a class of systems that are “not too far” from more classical limits. The insight here is that just including more and more freedom and shifting in the directions of this freedom doesn’t get you into the maximal-complexity picture: rather, it gets you into an interesting picture that provably (for sufficiently small perturbations) allows for an interesting amount of complexity with excellent simplifications and coarse-grainings, and deep math.

Phrased less poetically, I’m making a distinction between something being robust and making no assumptions. When thinking mathematically about alignment, what we need is the former. In particular, I predict that if we study systems in the vicinity of realistic (or possibly even toy) systems, even counting on some amount of misalignment pressure, alien complexity, and so on, the pure math we get will be very different – and indeed, I think much more elegant – than if we impose no assumptions at all. I think that someone with this intuition can still be quite pessimistic, can ask for very high levels of mathematical formalism, but will still expect a very high amount of insight and progress from interacting with real-world systems.

Dmitry VaintrobΩ47869

I think this is a really good and well-thought-out explanation of the agenda.

I do still think that it's missing a big piece: namely in your diagram, the lowest-tier dot (heuristic explanations) is carrying a lot of weight, and needs more support and better messaging. Specifically, my understanding having read this and interacted with ARC's agenda is that "heuristic arguments" as a direction is highly useful. But while it seems to me that the placement of heuristic arguments at the root of this ambitious diagram is core to the agenda, I haven't been convinced that this placement is supported by any results beyond somewhat vague associative arguments.

As an extreme example of this, Stephen Wolfram believes he has a collection of ideas building on some thinking about cellular automata that will describe all of physics. He can write down all kinds of causal diagrams with this node in the root, leading to great strides in our understanding of science and the cosmos and so on. But ultimately, such a diagram would be making the statement that "there exists a productive way to build a theory of everything which is based on cellular automata in a particular way similar to how he thinks about this theory". Note that this is different from saying that cellular automata are interesting, or even that a better theory of cellular automata would be useful for physics, and requires a lot more motivation and scientific falsification to motivate.

The idea of heuristic arguments is, at its core, a way of generalizing the notion of independence in statistical systems and models of statistical systems. It's discussing a way to point at a part of the system and say "we are treating this as noise" or "we are treating these two parts as statistically independent", or "we are treating these components of the system as independently as we can, given the following set of observations about our system" (with a lot of the theory of HA asking how to make the last of these statements explicit/computable). I think this is a productive class of questions to think about, both theoretically and empirically. It's related to a lot of other research in the field (on causality, independence and so on). I conceptually vibe with ARC's approach from what I've seen of the org. (Modulo the corrigible fact that I think there should be a lot more empirical work on what kinds of heuristic arguments work in practice. For example what's the right independence assumption on components of an image classifier/ generator NN that notices/generates the kind of textural randomness seen in a cat's fur? So far there is no HA guess about this question, and I think there should be at least some ideas on this level for the field to have a healthy amount of empiricism.)

I think that what ARC is doing is useful and productive. However, I don't see strong evidence that this particular kind of analysis is a principled thing to put at the root of a diagram of this shape. The statement that we should think about and understand independence is a priori not the same as the idea that we should have a more principled way of deciding when one interpretation of a neural net is more correct than another, which is also separate from (though plausibly related to) the (I think also good) idea in MAD/ELK that it might be useful to flag NN's that are behaving "unusually" without having a complete story of the unusual behavior.

I think there's an issue with building such a big structure on top of an undefended assumption, which is that it is creates some immissibility (i.e., difficulty of mixing) with other ideas in interpretability, which are "story-centric". The phenomena that happen in neural nets (same as phenomena in brains, same as phenomena in realistic physical systems) are probably special: they depend on some particular aspects of the world/ of reasoning/ of learning that has some sophisticated moving parts that aren't yet understood (some standard guesses are shallow and hierarchical dependence graphs, abundance of rough symmetries, separation of scale-specific behaviors, and so on). Our understanding will grow by capturing these ideas in terms of suitably natural language and sophistication for each phenomenon.

[added in edit] In particular (to point at a particular formalization of the general critique), I don't think that there currently exists a defendable link between Heuristic Arguments and the proof verification as in Jason Gross's excellent paper. The specific weakening of the notion of proof verification is more general interpretability. Your post on surprise accounting, is also excellent, but it doesn't explain how heuristic arguments would lead to understanding systems better -- rather, it shows that if we had ways of making better independence assumptions about systems with an existing interpretation, we would get a useful way of measuring surprise and explanatory robustness (with proof a maximally robust limit). But I think that drawing the line from seeking explanations with some nice properties/ measurements to the statement that a formal theory of such properties would lead to an immediate generalization of proof/interpretability which is strictly better than the existing "story-centric" methods is currently undefended (similar to the story that some early work on causality in interp had that a good attempt to formalize and validate causal interpretations would lead to better foundations of interp. -- the techniques are currently used productively e.g. here, but as an ingredient of an interpretation analysis rather than the core of the story). I think similar critiques hold for other sufficiently strong interpretations of the other arrows in this post. Note that while I would support a weaker meaning of arrows here (as you suggest in a footnote), there is nevertheless a core implicit assumption that the diagram exists as a part of a coherent agenda that deduces ambitious conclusions from a quite specific approach to interpretability. I could see any of the nodes here as being a part of a reasonable agenda that integrates with mechanistic interpretability more generally, but this is not the approach that ARC has followed.

I think that the issue of the approach sketched here is that it overindexes on a particular shape of explanation -- namely, that the most natural way to describe the relevant details inherent in principled interpretability work will most naturally factorize through a language that grows out of better-understanding independence assumptions in statistical modeling. I don't see much evidence for this being the case, any more than I see evidence that the best theory of physics should grow out of a particular way of seeing cellular automata (and I'd in fact bet with some confidence that this is not true in both of these cases). At the same time I think that ARC ideas are good, and that trying to relate them to other work in interp is productive (I'm excited about the VAE draft in particular). I just would like to see a less ambitious, more collaboratively motivated version of this, which is working on improving and better validating the assumptions one could make as part of mechanistic/statistical analysis of a model (with new interpretability/MAD ideas as a plausible side-effect) rather than orienting towards a world where this particular direction is in some sense foundational for a "universal theory of interpretability".

I don't think this is the whole story, but part of it is surely that a person motivating their actions by "wanting to be happy" is evidence for them being less satisfied/ happy than baseline

In particular, it's not hard to produce a computable function that isn't given by a polynomial-sized circuit (parity doesn't work as it's polynomial, but you can write one down using diagonalization -- it would be very long to compute, but computable in some suitably exponentially bounded time). But P vs. NP is not about this: it's a statement that exists fully in the world of polynomially computable functions.

Load More