Let R be a Euclidean_domain. Then R is a principal ideal domain.
This proof essentially mirrors the first proof one might find in the concrete case of the integers, if one sat down to discover an integer-specific proof; but we approachcast it from ainto slightly different direction,language using an equivalent definition of "ideal", because it is a bit cleaner that way.
It is a very useful exercise to work through the proof, using Z instead of the general ring R and using "size" [1] as the Euclidean function.
This proof essentially mirrors the first proof one might find in the concrete case of the integers, if one sat down to discover an integer-specific proof.proof; but we approach it from a slightly different direction, because it is a bit cleaner that way.
It is a very useful exercise to work through the proof, using Z instead of the general ring R and using "size" [1] as the Euclidean function.
We need to show that every ideal is principal, so take an ideal I⊆R.
IfWe'll view I as the kernel of a homomorphism=α{:0R}→S; recall that this is the proper way to think of ideals. (Proof of the equivalence.)
Then we need to show that there is some r∈R then we are immediately done: itsuch that α(x)=0 if and only if x is principal, being generated by the elementa multiple of r.
If α only sends 0.
So there is some nonzero element in to I0 (that is, everything else doesn't get sent to 0), then we're immediately done: just let r=0.
Otherwise, α sends something nonzero to 0; choose a nonzero element r to be nonzero with minimal ϕ.
We claim that the ideal is in fact generated bythis r. works.
Indeed, given anylet i∈I, we need i∈⟨r⟩x (the ideal generated bybe a multiple of r: that is, the set of all, so we can write it as ar, say.
Then α(ar)=α(a)α(r)=α(a)×0=0.
Therefore multiples of r) are sent by α to 0.
Conversely, if x is not a multiple of r doesn't divide, then we can write i, then we can find α and β such that ix=αar+βb withwhere ϕ(βb)<ϕ(r), since and ϕb is a Euclidean function. But thennonzero. i[2]
is in I, andThen α(x)=α(ar)+α(b) is in; we already have Iα(r)=0 (because r is in I);, so iα−(x)=αr(b must be in I, and hence β is in r).
But βb has a smaller ϕ-value than r does, and this contradicts the minimality ofwe picked r; so this bullet point can't happen after all.
So we have shown that α(x)=0 if and only if x is a multiple of r).
Therefore if i∈I then i∈⟨r⟩.
Conversely, if i∈⟨r⟩ then i is a multiple of r.
But r is in I already, so i must also be in i.
Hence I=⟨r⟩, so I is principal.as required.
This proof essentially mirrors the first proof one might find in the concrete case of the integers, if one sat down to discover an integer-specific proof. It is a very useful exercise to work through the proof, using Z instead of the general ring R and using "size" [1] as the Euclidean function.
Therefore if i∈I then i∈⟨r⟩.
Conversely, if i∈⟨r⟩ then i is a multiple of r. But r is in I already, so i must also be in i.
Hence I=⟨r⟩, so I is principal.
That is, if n>0 then the size is n; if n<0 then the size is −n. We just throw away the sign.
A common theme in ring theory is the idea that we identify a property of the integers, and work out what that property means in a more general setting.
The idea of the Euclidean_domain captures the fact that in Z, we may perform the division_algorithm (which can then be used to work out greatest common divisors and other such nice things from Z).
Here, we will prove that this simple property actually imposes a lot of structure on a ring: it forces the ring to be a principal ideal domain, so that every Ideal_ring_theoryideal has just one generator.
Let R be a Euclidean domain, and say ϕ:R∖{0}→N≥0 is a Euclidean function.
That is,
-
A common theme in ring theory is the idea that we identify a property of the integers, and work out what that property means in a more general setting. The idea of the Euclidean_domain captures the fact that in Z, we may perform the division_algorithm (which can then be used to work out greatest common divisors and other such nice things from Z). Here, we will prove that this simple property actually imposes a lot of structure on a ring: it forces the ring to be a principal ideal domain, so that every Ideal_ring_theory has just one generator.
In turn, this forces the ring to have unique factorisation (proof), so in some sense the Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic (i.e. the statement that Z is a unique factorisation domain) is true entirely because the division algorithm works in Z.
This result is essentially why we care about Euclidean domains: because if we know a Euclidean function for an integral domain, we have a very easy way of recognising that the ring is a principal ideal domain.
Let R be a Euclidean_domain. Then R is a principal ideal domain.
This proof essentially mirrors the first proof one might find in the concrete case of the integers, if one sat down to discover an integer-specific proof.
Let R be a Euclidean domain, and say ϕ:R∖{0}→N≥0 is a Euclidean function. That is, - if a divides b then ϕ(a)≤ϕ(b); - for every a, and every b not dividing a, we can find q and r such that a=qb+r and ϕ(r)<ϕ(b).
We need to show that every ideal is principal, so take an ideal I⊆R. If I={0} then we are immediately done: it is principal, being generated by the element 0.
So there is some nonzero element in I; choose a nonzero element r with minimal ϕ. We claim that the ideal is in fact generated by r.
Indeed, given any i∈I, we need i∈⟨r⟩ (the ideal generated by r: that is, the set of all multiples of r).
There do exist principal ideal domains which are not Euclidean domains: Z[12(1+√−19)] is an example. (Proof.)
The division_algorithm is a fundamental property of the integers, and it turns out that almost all of the nicest properties of the integers stem from the division algorithm. All rings which have the division algorithm (that is, Euclidean domains) are principal ideal domains: they have the property that every ideal has just one generator.