Some comments, organized by section.
3.1 If we accept the Vorlons' offer to create a stroke-free duplicate, that does not mean that we are claiming that the duplicate is the same (numerically identical) person. We could instead say that some things are more important than numerical identity, and that this is such a case. I think that's what we should say.
3.2 The reversal test for status quo bias is no good here, because which status is quo is relevant. The best way I can think of to explain this is an analogy. Take gold: a valuable substance which, we all know from our science classes, is atomic number 79. That is, we thought we knew. But the Vorlons appear in a hologram and explain that, as a result of their ancient war, the atomic numbers have been fluctuating and all that beautiful yellow jewelry is actually now atomic number 75 - we just failed to keep up with events. Atomic number 79 is now that stuff we call "bismuth". They explain a whole new physics of vorlonicles (as we name the new particles) showing that while the beautiful yellow jewelry was undergoing a change of atomic number, it still maintained characteristic invariant vorlonicle-structures, which allowed it to stay yellow, beautiful, heavy, and so on.
Does this mean you should go back to the jeweler's and yell at them for selling you fakes? Should you return your rings and demand a bottle of Pepto-Bismol instead? No, it means that the essential feature of gold never was its atomic number, despite appearances that it was so. Your jewelry is still golden, and that bottle of Pepto still contains bismuth.
Similarly, in Mark Walker's scenario, nobody was born yesterday, their children are still theirs, and somatic identity never had anything to do with personal identity, because the status was quo. The status quo in one's world, or more precisely the normal workings of things, determines the reference of one's terms. In the Vorlon-world "gold" refers to a certain invariant of vorlonicles - but in the real world, "gold" still refers to atomic number 79.
3.3 The Hatfield-McCoy argument fails. To see why, we just need to look at the obverse side of the coin. Thus: Hatfield hates McCoy so badly that he is willing to undergo radical changes in his personality and memory in exchange for killing McCoy. So he does. The surviving human being claims - with perfect sincerity! - not to remember hating McCoy, and to be a nonviolent person. If we accept psychological continuity as the public norm, Hatfield gets away - from his viewpoint, at least - with murder. The practical-ethical argument is a wash.
6.0. If P2''' were presented without argument:
Preservation of personal identity requires preservation of numerical [token] identity.
then it would indeed beg the question. But I can think of two good arguments for it right off the bat. First, types are abstract entities, and while we may be quite happy with abstract entities in logic, math and semantics, to posit that you are an abstract entity is quite a surprise. Second, people, like animals and insentient objects, are routinely identified and re-identified, and individuated, by bodily characteristics. I've never heard of two human bodies being considered one person based on psychological similarity. That just isn't how we normally think about people.
Which is not to deny that type-identity is important. But it can be important without its being equivalent to personal identity. See my comments on 3.1 above.
The token identity seems to me to be the part of identity that matters to me - it seems to be what this specific consciousness is, if that makes any sense.
(warning: this comment is merely personal ramblings)
For some reason, I find it easier to intuitively accept that a system of symbolic manipulations could be conscious than that I am a system of symbolic manipulations.
I find this strange because I also think that if symbolic manipulation could be conscious than I am very probably constituted of symbolic manipulation.
What I take away from this is that on the topic of consciousness such intuition is confused and hard to please. I should probably avoid using it yet I find myself unable to completely resign to such a plan.
Assuming a very low probability of your not being conscious, "A can be conscious" is strictly more likely than "I am a ".
If P(I'm a foobar) > P(A foobar can be conscious), then there are worlds where you are not conscious (and also a foobar). Assuming you are conscious, "I'm a foobar" becomes "A foobar can be conscious, and this specific thing is a conscious foobar", so P(I'm a foobar) <= P(A foobar can be conscious) and the equality holds only if you believe that if foobars can be conscious then you have to be one - that it is completely impossible to be some other kind of thing that is also conscious.
The important bit being that all this depends very little on what foobars are (not at all except the last assumption). It does depend on you being almost certainly conscious, but if you didn't have lots of evidence for it you wouldn't think much of this whole consciousness concept, now would you?
I feel like I am really missing something here. I don't see how the modal argument is supposed to work. I have lots of evidence that I am conscious in this world. But how is that evidence supposed to help when I move to a different world -- one in which I may or may not be a foobar?
At a first pass, I just don't know how to parse the claims you are making. Are you saying, for example, that P(I am a foobar in this world) < P(A foobar is conscious in this world), or P(I am a foobar in some possible world) < P(A foobar is conscious in some possible world), or ... ?
At a second pass, I'm not sure how to evaluate the probability of modal claims.
At a third pass, I'm worried that your argument equivocates on the interpretation of probability in your two assumptions. The first assumption -- that P(I'm a foobar) > P(A foobar can be conscious) -- seems to use a modal relative frequency interpretation: where the probability of an event is the frequency of possible worlds in which the event occurs. The second assumption -- that P(I'm conscious) is nearly one -- seems to use an evidentialist or maybe personalist view of probability. But I don't think these two can be combined unless you have some principle by which evidence that I am conscious in this world is also evidence that I am conscious in nearly every possible world.
Could you try explaining in more detail?
Could use some more clarity. The basic claim seems to be that we are valuable similar to how Shakespeare's handwritten Hamlet is valuable, but that it's better for an apprentice's copy of Hamlet to exist than none at all. Which I would agree with. But there seems to be a lot of unnecessary defining and pumping intuition hither and thither, without tackling the meaty stuff. The concept of assigning utilities may be helpful to map out this "not only valuing the original, but not treating copies as equally valuable" typical human fuzzy definition.
Also:
3.3 Against somaticism: practical ethics
Gaah, motivated stopping.
I think using the type-token distinction is a non-starter. The Shakespeare example illustrates why. A written text has a clear type-token distinction because writing is a system of convention. The information contained in a document is defined with reference to a set of public conventions. In the example there are two things about the document we might find valuable: that it is original and that it is complete. We would perhaps value completeness over originality under some circumstances, given the choice. But that we can value completeness is because we have a written document, a document created according to the public conventions of a language, a writing system, etc.
Consider that we discover an alien communications device somewhat analogous to a written note in human society. We know that this object is used to communicate information but we have no idea how the aliens communicate, how they encode that information in a permanent form, etc. We want to make a copy. How do we do it? The only thing we could do is to replicate the alien object in the somatic sense. We would have to be somaticists with regard to the alien object. Until we understood the public conventions underlying alien communication and the encoding of that communication there would be, for us, no such thing as merely copying the message contained in the device.
With a human being we're in a similar situation except that there just aren't any public conventions that would allow us to copy the "complete" human being in any other sense that the somaticist sense. So what sense can we make of the analogy between the contents of a document and the continuity of our psychological faculties? Take the example of the Vorlons copying us every day. This story is rather misleading since it assumes the psychological account from the outset; that there's a story about people being replaced every night, rather than a story about being 1-day old and being faced with the bizarre situation where a string of unrelated 1-day old people with false memories have preceded you. The situation really isn't any different, from a somaticist perspective, to being told we were all created last night and everything we remember is a fabrication. It seems to me that the continuity of our psychological faculties is a question of their reliability rather than their contents and clearly if my memories are the product of Vorlon manipulation, rather than some reliable process, then they are fake regardless of whether the Vorlons have created other such beings in the past.
I think these kind of bodily copying and destruction scenarios are just the sort of thing that undermines the reliability and hence continuity of our psychological faculties, so I'd argue that somaticism is true and of a necessary but not sufficient flavour and that the psychological account is necessarily dependent on bodily integrity over time. The two approaches are thus inseparable: to value psychological continuity is to value bodily integrity.
“Personal Identity and Uploading”, Mark Walker is the next JET paper. Abstract:
1 Uploading: prospects and perils
2 The equivalency thesis
The thesis disturbed me the first time I saw it; it seemed to me that it either begged the basic philosophical question at point or it did not do any work. So I read on to see how it was used. It seems to be the latter case: the thesis is barely used and not really germane to the examples that criticize somaticism and argue for a type-token kind of personal identity. This is good because it seems like used in any kind of strong sense, it’s easy to criticize the thesis.
(Implicitly, it seems to scope over all individuals - that we could rewrite it as, ‘for all individuals that survive any carbon->carbon transition, there is a carbon->silicon transition they survive’. But this seems false: a book is made out of carbon, survives minute to minute or copy to copy, and can be satisfactorily uploaded, but can a squishy human brain? Can a bowl of water? If I take a stick of carbon and light it on fire, how do I upload the burning stick? What does an uploaded diamond do? One might say the physics of the constituent atoms can be uploaded and this is a correct emulation with any necessary properties like emergence, but then we’re back to the question-begging.)
3 Personal identity: psychological and somatic accounts
3.1 Against somaticism: the big stroke
3.2 Against somaticism: retrospective replicas
This example reminds me strongly of Nick Bostrom’s reversal test for the status quo bias; an example would be a drug that increases IQ 10 points may be feared and rejected, but would it be accepted if scientists discovered new pollution will reduce IQ 10 points and that drug would compensate? I like his reversal test, and I like this example as well.
3.3 Against somaticism: practical ethics
4 No branching
(For those not familiar with the literature, ‘numerical’ here is being used in a sense of complete identity - there being complete logical equivalence. So for example, everyone reading this is numerically identical with themselves, and numerically not identical with the pope.)
5 Types and tokens
Walker invokes the type-token distinction:
for 2 false anti-replication personal-identity arguments:
The reader can guess what comes next: he’ll make the move of saying personal identity is the ‘type’ and any upload or copy is the ‘token’. We accept that while the original Hamlet is valuable in many respects, Hamlet survives the destruction of the original if an appropriately faithful copy is made.
6 The type/token solution to personal identity
Points in favor of the type-token:
7 Should I upload?
(This hearkens back to a previous JET paper I covered, “Ray Kurzweil and Uploading: Just Say No!”, Nick Agar. Agar is not cited for this part of the paper.)
8 Further reading
There doesn’t seem to be any discussion of this paper online. My own views on personal identity tend to the psychological pattern, which does not seem to be very different from a type-token theory of personal identity, if there is any meaningful difference at all, so this was a less challenging paper to read than the others, the equivalency thesis aside. The examples may be worth remembering.