There is a problem with the Turing test, practically and philosophically, and I would be willing to bet that the first entity to pass the test will not be conscious, or intelligent, or have whatever spark or quality the test is supposed to measure. And I hold this position while fully embracing materialism, and rejecting p-zombies or epiphenomenalism.
The problem is Campbell's law (or Goodhart's law):
The more any quantitative
socialindicator is used forsocialdecision-making, the more subject it will be to corruption pressures and the more apt it will be to distort and corrupt thesocialprocesses it is intended to monitor."
This applies to more than social indicators. To illustrate, imagine that you were a school inspector, tasked with assessing the all-round education of a group of 14-year old students. You engage them on the French revolution and they respond with pertinent contrasts between the Montagnards and Girondins. Your quizzes about the properties of prime numbers are answered with impressive speed, and, when asked, they can all play quite passable pieces from "Die Zauberflöte".
You feel tempted to give them the seal of approval... but they you learn that the principal had been expecting your questions (you don't vary them much), and that, in fact, the whole school has spent the last three years doing nothing but studying 18th century France, number theory and Mozart operas - day after day after day. Now you're less impressed. You can still conclude that the students have some technical ability, but you can't assess their all-round level of education.
The Turing test functions in the same way. Imagine no-one had heard of the test, and someone created a putative AI, designing it to, say, track rats efficiently across the city. You sit this anti-rat-AI down and give it a Turing test - and, to your astonishment, it passes. You could now conclude that it was (very likely) a genuinely conscious or intelligent entity.
But this is not the case: nearly everyone's heard of the Turing test. So the first machines to pass will be dedicated systems, specifically designed to get through the test. Their whole setup will be constructed to maximise "passing the test", not to "being intelligent" or whatever we want the test to measure (the fact we have difficulty stating what exactly the test should be measuring shows the difficulty here).
Of course, this is a matter of degree, not of kind: a machine that passed the Turing test would still be rather nifty, and as the test got longer, and more complicated, as the interactions between subject and judge got more intricate, our confidence that we were facing a truly intelligence machine would increase.
But degree can go a long way. Watson won on Jeopardy without exhibiting any of the skills of a truly intelligent being - apart from one: answering Jeopardy questions. With the rise of big data and statistical algorithms, I would certainly rate it as plausible that we could create beings that are nearly perfectly conscious from a (textual) linguistic perspective. These "super-chatterbots" could only be identified as such with long and tedious effort. And yet they would demonstrate none of the other attributes of intelligence: chattering is all they're any good at (if you ask them to do any planning, for instance, they'll come up with designs that sound good but fail: they parrot back other people's plans with minimal modifications). These would be the closest plausible analogues to p-zombies.
The best way to avoid this is to create more varied analogues of the Turing test - and to keep them secret. Just as you keep the training set and the test set distinct in machine learning, you want to confront the putative AIs with quasi-Turing tests that their designers will not have encountered or planed for. Mix up the test conditions, add extra requirements, change what is being measured, do something completely different, be unfair: do things that a genuine intelligence would deal with, but an overtrained narrow statistical machine couldn't.
What do you mean by "intelligent conversation" ? Do you mean, "a conversation with an intelligent agent", or "a conversation whose contents satisfy certain criteria", and if so, which ones ? I'll assume you mean the former for now.
Let's say that you had a text-only chat with the agent, and found it intellectually stimulating. You thought that the agent was responding quite cleverly to your comments, had a distinct "writer's voice", etc.
Now, let's imagine two separate worlds. In world A, you learned that the agent was in fact a GLUT. Surprised and confused, you confronted it in conversation, and it responded to your comments as it did before, with apparent intelligence and wit. But, of course, now you knew better than to fall for such obvious attempts to fool you.
In world B, the exact same thing happened, and the rest of your conversation proceeded as before, with one minor difference: unbeknownst to you, the person who told you that the agent was a GLUT was himself a troll. He totally gaslighted you. The agent isn't a GLUT or even an AI; it's just a regular human (and the troll's accomplice), a la the good old Mechanical Turk.
It sounds to me like if you were in world B, you'd still disbelieve that you were having a conversation with an intelligent agent. But in world B, you'd be wrong. In world A, you would of course be right.
Is there any way for you to tell which world you're in (I mean, without waterboarding that pesky troll or taking apart the Chinese Room to see who's inside, etc.) ? If there is no way for you to tell the difference, then what's the difference ?
By the way, I do agree with you that, in our real world, the probability of such a GLUT existing is pretty much zero. I am merely questioning the direction of your (hypothetical) belief update.
By construction, there's no way for me to tell... that is, I've already posited that some event (somehow, implausibly) convinced me my interlocutor is a GLUT.
In world A, "I" was correct to be convinced; my interlocutor really was (somehow, implausibly) a GLUT, impossible as that seems. In world B, "I" was (somehow, implausibly) incorrectly convinced.
There's all kinds of things I can be fooled about, and knowing that I can be fooled about those things should (and does) make me more difficult to convince of them. But if, even taking tha... (read more)