I imagine the relationship differently. I imagine a relationship between how well a system can perform a task and the number of tasks the same system can accomplish.
Does a chicken have a general intelligence? A chicken can perform a wide range of tasks with low performance, and performs most tasks worse than random. For example, could a chicken solve a Rubik's Cube? I think it would perform worse than random.
Generality to me seems like an aggregation of many specialised processes working together seamlessly to achieve a wide variety of tasks. Where do humans sit on my scale? I think we are pretty far along the x axis, but not too far up the y axis.
For your orthogonality thesis to be right, you have to demonstrate the existence of a system that's very far along the x axis but exactly zero on the y axis. I argue that such a system is equivalent to a system that sits at zero in both the x and y axes, and hence we have a counterexample.
Imagine a general intelligence (e.g. a human) with damage to a certain specialised part of their brain, e.g. short-term memory. They will have the ability to do a very wide variety of tasks, but they will struggle to play chess.
Jeff Dean has proposed a new approach to ML he calls System Pathways in which we connect many ML models together such that when one model learns, it can share its learnings with other models so that the aggregate system can be used to achieve a wide variety of tasks.
This would reduce duplicate learning. Sometimes two specialised models end up learning the same thing, but when those models are connected together, we only need to do the learning once and then share it.
If Turing Completeness turns out to be all we need to create a general intelligence, then I argue that any entity capable of creating computers is generally intelligent. The only living organism we know of that has succeeded in creating a computer is the humans. Creating computers seems to be some kind of intelligence escape velocity. Once you create computers, you can create more intelligence (and maybe destroy yourself and those around you in the process).
Regarding the counterexample: I think it is fair to say that perfect orthogonality is not plausible, especially not if we allow cases with one axis being zero, whatever that might mean. But intelligence and generality could be still largely orthogonal. What do you think of the case of insects, as an example of low intelligence and high generality?
(I think not even the original orthogonality thesis holds perfectly. An example is the oft-cited fact that animals don't optimize for the goal of inclusive genetic fitness because they are not intelligent enough to grasp such a goal. So they instead optimize for similar things, like sex.)
Have you come across the work of Yann LeCun on world models? LeCun is very interested in generality. He calls generality the "dark matter of intelligence". He thinks that to achieve a high degree of generality, the agent needs to construct world models.
Insects have highly simplified world models, and that could be part of the explanation for the high degree of generality exhibited by insects. For example, the fact the male Jewel Beetle fell in love with beer bottles mistaking them for females is strong evidence that beetles have highly simplified world models.
I see what you mean now. I like the example of insects. They certainly do have an extremely high degree of generality despite their very low level of intelligence.
We can demonstrate this wth a test.
I just think that randomness is a useful benchmark for performance on accomplishing tasks.
In Bogosort, the lower bound for random version is unbounded which is O(inf). You can even turn the Rubiks Cube problem into a sorting problem of finding path from starting position to solved position, involving a series of moves. I'm not sure if there are more than one set of shortest path solution to each scenario.
Oh, I'm not making the argument that randomly permuting the Rubik's Cube will always solve it in a finite time, but that it might. I think it has a better chance of solving it than the chicken. The chicken might get lucky and knock the Rubik's Cube off the edge of a cliff and it might rotate by accident, but other than that, the chicken isn't going to do much work on solving it in the first place. Meanwhile, randomly permuting might solve it (or might not solve it in the worst case). I just think that random permutations have a higher chance of solving it than the chicken, but I can't formally prove that.
"A specialist is like a boil: its fullness is one-sided" -- Kozma Prutkov
A (semi-fictional) example that comes to mind is the protagonist of Rain man, and similar idiot savant stereotypes.
I think a better approach would be not black and white orthogonality, but the degree of correlation. In humans there is definitely a variety of specialization at high intelligence levels (e.g. there are polymaths like Feynman who can excel in many disparate activities to the degree an average human would not, but also those who only excel in one area, say, music, and suck at life in general), but also hints that smarter people are on average smarter in multiple areas. There are probably studies out there that research correlation between intelligence and specialization, I wonder if you did a literature review?
I think what people mean by intelligence is how well someone or something does on tests, stuff you measure with precision and recall. Then you do some arithmetic and you get a number, whether it's how many pieces of music you wrote or how many answers you got correct. Anything about intelligence outside of this context is actually a misnomer. They are rather talking about the process where the measure of intelligence can be deduced. A lot of it is dependent on the measurement of speed. That's why they usually give you time limit for shit like this.
I think you have it backwards. Tests measure or purport to measure intelligence, but most people can tell a smart person from a not so smart one, though this can vary by domain.
Since intelligence is an arbitrary value on completely different processes in different context, I don't know if you can call tests a measurement of such construct. Generally, it's mostly a measure of 1) good memory and 2) the speed of the look up. If you have good memory but slow, you won't be able to make practical use of the good memory, or at least maximizing its potential. If you have shit memory but fast look up, then you can specialize and do that for the rest of your life and be good at it, improving your look up time over the years. 3) The next layer is measuring the quality of the look up. 1 is dataset, 2 is running time, 3 is tuning the weights.
The term intelligence bears no actual meaning without some form of concrete measurement.
I think there are two interesting questions relating to this:
Sorry - forgot about your comment.
Tasks that animals usually face? (Find food, a safe place to sleep, survive, reproduce ...)
This is an intriguing question. My first intuition: Probably not, because ...
On the other hand, perhaps there is indeed a higher level of generality, just not one which is a low-hanging fruit. Or one which is at least not a low-hanging fruit for the neuron-based brain structure which evolution on Earth is using in animals. (For example, brains are highly parallel but very slow in serial tasks, while silicon processors have a much higher serial speed. From computational complexity theory it is known that not all algorithms can be parallelized efficiently.)
Another possibility is that some higher level of generality simply needs a certain amount of intelligence in order to "work". Which would mean that at some point in increasing intelligence, a phase-transition to a higher generality level would occur. The reason this has not happened yet in the history of evolution would simply be that a sufficient level of intelligence was not yet achieved.
Thinking of it, one possible example for the latter having already happened once could be: cultural evolution. Only humans can (due to language, but also due to high intelligence) accumulate information across generations, learn, and adapt via culture instead of just via genes. That would indeed contradict my theory that humans are not significantly more general than other animals. If we accept the emergence of cultural evolution in humans as a phase transition to a higher level of generality, then there could be still other levels, inaccessible to us, but possibly accessible to a highly intelligent AI.
Edit: Actually there were at least two phase transitions in "learning methods" of the above kind: Once via the emergence of cultural evolution some hundred thousand years ago, and once via the emergence of brains some hundred million years ago. If evolution is already some kind of learning process, then organisms with brains add one layer, and our "cultural" layer is a further one on top.
But classical chess computers like DeepBlue rely a lot on raw compute, yet this brute force approach is fairly useless in cases with large search space, like Go. I think the number of parameters in a neural network would be a better approximation.
Then we can even make the scaling hypothesis more precise: Presumably it says scaling is enough for (more) intelligence_1, but not for generality.
A common presupposition seems to be that intelligent systems can be classified on two axes:
For example, AlphaGo is presumably fairly intelligent, but quite narrow, while humans are both quite intelligent and quite general.
A natural hypothesis would be that these two axes are orthogonal, such that any combination of intelligence and generality is possible.
Surprisingly, I know of nobody who has explicitly spelt out this new orthogonality thesis, let alone argued for or against it.
(The original orthogonality thesis only states that level of intelligence and terminal goals are independent. It does not talk about the narrow/general distinction.)
MIRI seems to be not very explicit about this, too. On Arbital there are no separate entries for the notions of intelligence and generality, and the article on General Intelligence is rather vague. It appears to mix the two notions together. What I find most surprising: the article suggests that chimpanzees are substantially less general than humans. But it seems to me that chimpanzees are merely less intelligent than humans, not less general by a relevant amount. Just like AlphaGo's internal predecessor was presumably not less general than AlphaGo, just less intelligent.
What makes AlphaGo fairly narrow, apparently, is that it has a fairly small cognitive domain. I would even go so far and argue that most animals are highly general agents, since they have what MIRI calls a real-world domain.
Evolutionary speaking, constant optimization for high generality makes sense. Over several hundred million years of evolution, animals had to contionously survive in a diverse, noisy, and changing environment, and they had to compete with other animals. Under such evolutionary presurres, narrow specialization would quickly be punished. So most animals have evolved to be very general, just not always very intelligent. (Insects, presumably, are an example of fairly high generality but quite low intelligence.)
One could argue against this by claiming that the new orthogonality thesis is false. But then it is not clear how the narrow/general distinction is different from the low/high intelligence distinction.
Matthew Barnett suggests to me that what we commonly mean with "intelligence" is really a multiplicative combination of generality and (what I called) intelligence:
Intelligence2=Generality×Intelligence1
That is, intuitively we would not call something "intelligent" when it does not have a sufficient amount of both generality and (what I called) intelligence. Case in point: A very narrow AI perhaps does not seem intelligent, even if it is very good within its narrow domain. For such a multiplicative notion of intelligence the new orthogonality thesis would not hold.
But whatever we call it, there seems to be some notion of intelligence which is orthogonal to generality.
Or are there counterexamples?