Upvoted for the addition to our collective and to my personal vocabulary. I've encountered a small number of people who fit this pattern (different context; almost certainly nobody you know) and it's helpful to have a memorable cognitive handle for it.
This post feels like it may have been written in response to some specific interpersonal drama. If it was, then I'd like to make it clear that I have absolutely no idea what it was and therefore no opinion on it. I just think this is a useful concept in general.
I do have one minor nitpick:
...and three people complain of deeply unpleasant experiences with one of the organizers.
It's not clear to me whether, in this example, all three complaints are about the same organizer. It seems like they probably are, from context, but this could be written more clearly.
I think that representation is best explained as both correspondence and the outcome of optimization - specifically, representation is some sort of correspondence (which can be loose) that is caused by some sort of optimization process.
I'll speak primarily in defense of correspondence since I think that is where we disagree.
"All models are wrong, but some are useful" is a common aphorism in statistics, and I think it is helpful here too. You seem to treat mistaken representations as a separate sort of representation. However, even an ordinarily correct representation can contain some mistaken elements. For example:
Likewise ordinarily mistaken representations can contain correct elements:
There are also edge cases where a representation mixes correct and incorrect elements, such that it isn't clear whether we should call it a mistaken representation or not:
This suggests that it is useful to stop thinking about mistaken and correct representations as separate types, but rather to think about representations having mistaken and correct elements.
Having made this shift, I think that the correspondence theory of representation becomes viable again. Even a representation that is conventionally classified as mistaken may contain many correct elements - enough correct elements to make it about whatever it is about. A child's representation of Santa Claus contains many correct elements (often wears red, jolly, brings presents) and one very prominent incorrect element (the child thinks that Santa physically exists rather than being a well-known fiction). It may very well be the case that most of the bits in the child's representation are correct; we just pay more attention to the few that are wrong. For another example: if I think that I see a horse, but I actually see a cow at night, the correct elements include "it looks like a horse to me," and "it's that thing over there that I'm looking at right now." There's a lot of specificity in that last correct element! I think that's enough to make my representation be about the cow.
On the other hand, we can consider examples where an optimization process exists but where it fails to create correspondence:
With that being said, I do agree with you that optimization is an important piece of the puzzle - but not becasue it can explain how something can be about something else even if it is mistaken. Rather, I think that optimization is the answer to the problem of coincidences. For example:
Adding the second criteria - that the correspondence must be caused by an optimization process - prevents a definition of representation from identifying coincidences as representations.