I'm generally a fan of "maximize economic surplus and then split the benefits fairly". And I think this approach makes the most sense in contexts where agents are bargaining over a joint action space , where  is some object-level decision being made and  are side-payments that agents can use to transfer value between them.[1]

An example would be a negotiation between Alice and Bob over how to split a pile of  tokens, which Alice can exchange for  each, and Bob can exchange for  each. The sort of situation where there's a real and interpersonally comparable difference in the value they each derive from their least and most favorite outcome.[2]

In this example  is the convex set containing joint utilities for all splits of  tokens, and the  disagreement point. If we take ,  the Nash and KS bargaining solutions are for Alice and Bob to each receive  tokens. But this is clearly not actually Pareto optimal. Pareto optimality looks like enacting a binding agreement between Alice and Bob that "Bob can have all the tokens, and Alice receives a fair split of the money". And I claim the mistake was in modelling  as the full set of feasible options, when in fact the world around us redunds with opportunities to do better.

Side payments introduce important geometric information that  alone doesn't convey: the real-world tradeoff between making Alice happier and making Bob happier. Bargaining solutions are rightly designed to ignore how utility functions are shifted and scaled, and when  is compact we can standardize each agent's utility into 

A Standardized Flat Pareto Frontier for 2 Agents
A Standardized Flat Pareto Frontier for 2 Agents

With  alone, we can't distinguish between "Bob is just using bigger numbers to measure his utility" (measuring this standardized shape in nano-utilons) and "Bob is actually 1 billion times more sensitive to the difference between his least and most favorite outcome than Alice is."

In this example, when we project the outcome space into standardized joint utility space, the results for  and  look like that image above: a line sloping down from Bob's favorite outcome to Alice's, and all the space between that line and . And the Nash and KS bargaining solutions will be the same:  standardized utilons for each. But when we reverse the projection to find outcomes with this joint utility, for  we find ( tokens for Alice,  tokens for Bob), and for  we find (( tokens for Alice,  tokens for Bob), Bob gives Alice ).

Economists call "the resource used to measure value" the numéraire, and usually this unit of caring is money. If we can find or invent a resource that Alice and Bob both value linearly, economists say that they have quasilinear utility functions, which is amazing news. They can use this resource for side payments, it simplifies a lot of calculations, and it also causes agreement among many different ways we might try to measure surplus.

When Alice and Bob each have enough of this resource to pay for any movement across D, then the Pareto frontier of  becomes completely flat. And whenever this happens to a Pareto frontier, the Nash and KS bargaining solutions coincide exactly with "maximize economic surplus and split it equally."

"Maximize total utility" and "maximize average utility" are type errors if we interpret them literally. But "maximize economic surplus (and split it fairly)" is something we can do, using tools like trade and side payments to establish a common currency for surplus measurement.

Using Weights as Side Payments

Money is a pretty reasonable type of side-payment, but we could also let agents transfer weights in the joint utility function among themselves. This is the approach Andrew Critch explores in his excellent paper on Negotiable Reinforcement Learning, in which a single RL agent is asked to balance between the interests of multiple principals with different beliefs. The overall agent is an  maximizer, where the Harsanyi weights shift according to Bayes rule, giving better predictors more weight in future decisions. The principals essentially bet about the next observation the RL agent will make, where the stakes are denominated in .

One direction Andrew points towards for future work is using some kind of bargaining among sub-agents to determine what the overall agent does. One way to model this is by swapping out  maximization for  maximization, defining each agent's baseline if no trade takes place, and enriching  to include side payments.

  1. ^

    This can also be framed as picking a point on the Pareto frontier, and then letting agents pay each other for small shifts from there. Bargaining over  combines these into a single step.

  2. ^

    How do I know utilities can be compared? Exactly because when Bob offers Alice  for one of her tokens, she says "yep that sounds good to me!" Money is the unit of caring.

New Comment
4 comments, sorted by Click to highlight new comments since:
[-]aphyer3-2

I don't actually think 'Alice gets half the money' is the fair allocation in your example.

Imagine Alice and Bob splitting a pile of 100 tokens, which either of them can exchange for $10M each.  It seems obvious that the fair split here involves each of them ending up with $500M.

To say that the fair split in your example is for each player to end up with $500M is to place literally zero value on 'token-exchange rate', which seems unlikely to be the right resolution.

This might be a framing thing!

The background details I’d been imagining are that Alive and Bob were in essentially identical situations before their interaction, and it was just luck that Alice and Bob got the capabilities they did.

Alice and Bob have two ways to convert tokens into money, and I’d claim that any rational joint strategy involves only using Bob’s way. Alice's ability to convert tokens into pennies is a red herring that any rational group should ignore.

At that point, it's just a bargaining game over how to split the $1,000,000,000. And I claim that game is symmetric, since they’re both equally necessary for that surplus to come into existence.

If Bob had instead paid huge costs to create the ability to turn tokens into tens of millions of dollars, I totally think his costs should be repaid before splitting the remaining surplus fairly.

I'm generally a fan of "maximize economic surplus and then split the benefits fairly".

I kind of agree, from an outside controller's perspective.  Unfortunately, in the real universe, there is no outside controller, and there is no authority to make agents agree on either "maximum total surplus" or "fair".  In the embedded agency model (agents are independent and imperfect, and there is no outside view), the best you can do is for each agent to maximize their own utility, by sharing information that usually improves overall surplus.  Limiting it to economic/comparable values is convenient, but also very inaccurate for all known agents - utility is private and incomparable.

That said, side-payments are CRITICAL in finding solutions that do increase the total.  It turns a lot of zero-sum games into positive-sum games where cooperation is the obvious equilibrium.

Note that your example shares some aspects of the ultimatum game - a purely rational Alice should not expect/demand more than $1.00, which is the maximum she could get from the best possible (for her) split without side payments.  Only in a world where she knows and cares about Bob's situation and the cultural feelings of "fairness" indicate she "should" enjoy some of his situational benefits does she demand more.  

Limiting it to economic/comparable values is convenient, but also very inaccurate for all known agents - utility is private and incomparable.

I think modeling utility functions as private information makes a lot of sense! One of the claims I’m making in this post is that utility valuations can be elicited and therefore compared.

My go-to example of an honest mechanism is a second-price auction, which we know we can implement from within the universe. The bids serve as a credible signal of valuation, and if everyone follows their incentives they’ll bid honestly. The person that values the item the most is declared the winner, and economic surplus is maximized.

(Assuming some background facts, which aren't always true in practice, like everyone having enough money to express their preferences through bids. I used tokens in this example so that “willingness to pay” and “ability to pay” can always line up.)

We use the same technique when we talk about the gains from trade, which I think the Ultimatum game is intended to model. If a merchant values a shirt at $5, and I value it at $15, then there's $10 of surplus to be split if we can agree on a price in that range.

Bob values the tokens more than Alice does. We can tell because he can buy them from her at a price she's willing to accept. Side payments let us interpersonally compare valuations.

As I understand it, economic surplus isn't a subjective quantity. It's a measure of how much people would be willing to pay to go from the status quo to some better outcome. Which might start out as private information in people's heads, but there is an objective answer and we can elicit the information needed to compute and maximize it.

a purely rational Alice should not expect/demand more than $1.00, which is the maximum she could get from the best possible (for her) split without side payments.

I don't know of any results that suggest this should be true! My understanding of the classic analysis of the Ultimatum game is that if Bob makes a take-it-or-leave-it offer to Alice, where she would receive any tiny amount of money like $0.01, she should take it because $0.01 is better than $0.

My current take is that CDT-style thinking has crippled huge parts of economics and decision theory. The agreement of both parties is needed for this $1,000,000,000 of surplus to exist, if either walk away they both get nothing. The Ultimatum game is symmetric and the gains should be split symmetrically.

If we actually found ourselves in this situation, would we actually accept $1 out of $1 billion? Is that how we’d program a computer to handle this situation on our behalf? Is that the sort of reputation we’d want to be known for?