Review

I've only watched some prediction market news from the outside, so forgive my basic question, but are prediction markets supposed to bring in money besides having new entrants bring in cash?

I've often seen prediction markets compared to stock markets, but the stock market is generally positive-sum because you're investing money in profitable businesses that pay dividends. In contrast, if a prediction market begins with 1000 people with $1000 each (and no one else joins or brings in more money), can it ever have more than $1,000,000 in the market?

If the answer is "no, it doesn't generate money", isn't that a big problem for prediction markets as a long-term concept? It means everyone will be fighting over a limited pie, and there will be no reason for the average person to join the prediction market (they just stand to lose their money to the experts). Is this a problem holding back prediction markets now, and are there ideas to fix it? 

New Answer
New Comment

6 Answers sorted by

Multicore

4428

You are right that by default prediction markets do not generate money, and this can mean traders have little incentive to trade.

Sometimes this doesn't even matter. Sports betting is very popular even though it's usually negative sum.

Otherwise, trading could be stimulated by having someone who wants to know the answer to a question provide a subsidy to the market on that question, effectively paying traders to reveal their information. The subsidy can take the form of a bot that bets at suboptimal prices, or a cash prize for the best performing trader, or many other things.

Alternately, there could be traders who want shares of YES or NO in a market as a hedge against that outcome negatively affecting their life or business, who will buy even if the EV is negative, and other traders can make money off them.

Sometimes this doesn't even matter. Sports betting is very popular even though it's usually negative sum.


Yes. PredictIt used to attract a lot of "dumb money" - people who just wanted to bet on their favorite candidate (or against disfavored candidates). They also used to run weekly markets on polling averages and things like the number of times Trump would tweet that tended to attract people who just wanted to do some skill-based gambling, whether they actually had the skill or not.

PredictIt charges high transaction fees with no outside subsidies, so all o... (read more)

1M. Y. Zuo
The sports betting analogy is very apt. I would argue the negative effectives of losing big on prediction markets are still better then the negative effects of losing big on sports betting markets.

Thanks for the excellent answer!

On first blush, I'd respond with something like "but there's no way that's enough!" I think I see prediction markets as (potentially) providing a lot of useful information publicly, but needing a flow of money to compensate people for risk-aversion, the cost of research, and to overcome market friction. Of your answers:

  • Negative-sum betting probably doesn't scale well, especially to more technical and less dramatic questions.
  • Subsidies make sense, but could they run into a tragedy-of-the-commons scenario? For instance, if a gr
... (read more)
2Garrett Baker
I don't think this reasoning is entirely correct. The firm's choice depends on how much extra information-value marginal increases in liquidity have in the market. If the marginal dollar increases information value more when spent in providing liquidity to a prediction market than on internal research, then prediction markets will get funded more. Reason to think this is in general the case for many firms: Specialization and fewer transaction costs for hiring/making deals with consulting agencies.

Dagon

41

In theory, there can be information-seekers who subsidize either the operation of the market, or the payout pool for specific questions, or provide bonuses for profitable investors/market-adjusters.

But fundamentally, there's no "outside" source of income to participants, like there is for stock ownership (theoretically; there's a LOT of companies who've never paid a dividend).

Sinclair Chen

40

It’s not zero net value because there’s information produced, and also it’s fun. A more rational alien species that does not find risk enjoyable would have less accurate prediction markets (although without such thing as “gambling” maybe their markets are actually legal and thus more accurate.)

At manifold we haven’t really found a good way to use the information value yet. Subsidization doesn’t lead to increased activity in practice unless it makes the market among the top best trading opportunities. Pay for views has been much more effective as a “pay for information” method than subsidy. Most users are bettors rather than viewers. It’s good that we’re good at converting people, but without a long tail of lurkers we aren’t generating a lot of value from the information itself.

Cool to hear from someone at manifold about this! I agree the information and enjoyment value can make it worthwhile (and even pro-social), but if it's zero net monetary value, that surely limits their reach. I appreciate prediction markets from a perspective of "you know all that energy going into determining stock prices? That could be put towards something more useful!", but I worry they won't live up to that without a constant flow of money.

Subsidization doesn’t lead to increased activity in practice unless it makes the market among the top best tradin

... (read more)
1Sinclair Chen
Well, you can monetize info value in various ways - sell advertisements, subscriptions to get more data, access to superforecasters, directly sell “accuracy” (pay to increase trading volume) - if it is actually valuable. Alternatively, EA would probably continue to fund manifold if they find it valuable (like for pushing back AI timelines), but i still much prefer “valuable enough for people to pay for” as an objective target to hit. I think fun mostly causes traders to accept higher losses than they would otherwise. I don’t think it’s surprising that people don’t bet on profitable markets unless they actually know the market exists and they know there’s alpha in it. The whole purpose of marketing is to match users with deals they find valuable. And yet, do you think you have purchased every consumer good that would improve your life?

David Johnston

30

There is a situation in which information markets could be positive sum, though I don't know how practical it is:

I own a majority stake in company X. Someone has proposed an action A that company X take, I currently think this is worse than the status quo, but I think it's plausible that with better information I'd change my mind. I set up an exchange of X-shares-conditional-on-A for USD-conditional-on-A and the analogous exchange conditional on not-A, subsidised by some fraction of my X shares using an automatic market maker. If, by the closing date, X-shares-conditional-on-A trade at a sufficient premium to X-shares-conditional-on-not-A, I do A.

In this situation, my actions lose money vs the counterfactual of doing A and not subsidising the market, but compared to the counterfactual of not subsidising the market and not doing A I gain money because the rest of my stock is now worth more. It's unclear how I do compared to the most realistic counterfactual of "spend $Y researching action A more deeply and act accordingly".

(note that conditional prediction markets also have incentive issues WRT converging to the correct prices, though I'm not sure how important these are in practice)

Qumeric

3-7

In a good prediction market design users would not bet USD but instead something which appreciates over time or generates income (e.g. ETH, Gold, S&P 500 ETF, Treasury Notes, or liquid and safe USD-backed positions in some DeFi protocol).

Another approach would be to use funds held in the market to invest in something profit-generating and distribute part of the income to users. This is the same model which non-algorithmic stablecoins (USDT, USDC) use.

So it's a problem, but definitely a solvable one, even easily solvable. The major problem is that prediction markets are basically illegal in the US (and probably some other countries as well).

Also, Manifold solves it in a different way -- positions are used to receive loans, so you can free your liquidity from long (timewise) markets and use it to e.g. leverage. The loans are automatically repaid when you sell your positions. It is easy for Manifold because it doesn't use real money, but the same concept can be implemented in the "real" markets, although it would be more challenging (there will be occasional losses for the provider due to bad debt but it's the same with any other kind of credit, it can be managed).

In a good prediction market design users would not bet USD but instead something which appreciates over time or generates income (e.g. ETH, Gold, S&P 500 ETF, Treasury Notes, or liquid and safe USD-backed positions in some DeFi protocol).

Isn't this just changing the denominator without changing the zero- or negative-sum nature? If everyone shows up to your prediction market with 1 ETH instead of $1k, the total amount of ETH in the market won't increase, just as the total amount of USD would not have increased. Maybe "buy ETH and gamble it" has a better... (read more)

-1Qumeric
I feel like you are mixing two problems here: an ethical problem and a practical problem. UPD: on second thought, maybe you just meant the second problem, but still I think my response would be clearer by considering them separately. The ethical problem is that it looks like prediction markets do not generate income, thus they are not useful and shouldn't be endorsed, they don't differ much from gambling.  While it's true that they don't generate income and are zero-sum games in a strictly monetary sense, they do generate positive externalities. For example, there could be a prediction market about an increase of <insert a metric here> after implementing some policy.  The market will allow us to estimate the policy efficiently and make better decisions. Therefore, the market will be positive-sum because of the "better judgement" externality. The practical problem is that the zero-sum monetary nature of prediction markets disincentives participation (especially in year+ long markets) because on average it's more profitable to invest in something else (e.g. S&P 500). It can be solved by allowing to bet other assets, so people would bet their S&P 500 shares and on average get the same expected value, so it will be not disincentivising anymore. Also, there are many cases where positive externalities can be beneficial for some particular entity. For example, an investment company may want to know about the risk of a war in a particular country to decide if they want to invest in the country or not. In such cases, the company can provide rewards for market participants and make it a positive-sum game for them even from the monetary perspective. This approach is beneficial and used in practice, however, it is not always applicable and also can be combined with other approaches. Additionally, I would like to note that there is no difference between ETH and "giving a loan to a business" from a mechanism design perspective, you could tokenize your loan (and it's not cry
1Robert_AIZI
I think we're in agreement here. My concern is "prediction markets could be generating positive externalities for society, but if they aren't positive-sum for the typical user, they will be underinvested in (relative to what is societally optimal), and there may be insufficient market mechanisms to fix this". See my other comment here.
1Qumeric
Good to know :) I do agree that subsidies run into a tragedy-of-commons scenario. So despite subsidies are beneficial, they are not sufficient. But do you find my solution to be satisfactory? I thought about it a lot, I even seriously considered launching my own prediction market and wrote some code for it. I strongly believe that simply allowing the usage of other assets solves most of the practical problems, so I would be happy to hear any concerns or further clarify my point. Or another, perhaps easier solution (I updated my original answer):  just allow the market company/protocol to invest the money which are "locked" until resolution to some profit generating strategy and share the profit with users. Of course, it should be diversified, both in terms of investment portfolio and across individual markets (users get the same annual rate of return, no matter what particular thing they bet on). It has some advantages and disadvantages, but I think it's a more clear-cut solution.
2Robert_AIZI
This might not be the problem you're trying to solve, but I think if predictions markets are going to break into normal society they need to solve "why should a normie who is somewhat risk-averse, doesn't enjoy wagering for its own sake, and doesn't care about the information externalities, engage with prediction markets". That question for stock markets is solved via the stock market being overall positive-sum, because loaning money to a business is fundamentally capable of generating returns. Now let me read your answer from that perspective: Why not just hold Treasury Notes or my other favorite asset? What does the prediction market add? Why wouldn't I just put my funds directly into something profit-generating? I appreciate that less than 100% of my funds will be tied up in the prediction market, but why tie up any?  But once I have an S&P 500 share, why would I want to put it in a prediction market (again, assuming I'm a normie who is somewhat risk-averse, etc) So if I put $1000 into a prediction market, I can get a $1000 loan (or a larger loan using my $1000 EV wager as collateral)? But why wouldn't I just get a loan using my $1000 cash as collateral? Overall I feel listed several mechanisms that mitigate potential downsides of prediction markets, but they still pull in a negative direction, and there's no solid upside to a regular person who doesn't want to wager money for wager's sake, doesn't think they can beat the market, and is somewhat risk averse (which I think is a huge portion of the public). This I see as workable, but runs into a scale issue and the tragedy of the commons. Let's make up a number and say the market needs a 1% return on average to make it worthwhile after transaction fees, time investment, risk, etc. Then $X of incentive could motivate $100X of prediction market. But I think the issue of free-riders makes it very hard to scale X so that $100X ≈ [the stock market]. Overall, in order to make prediction markets sustainably larg
1Qumeric
Thanks, I think I understand your concern well now. I am generally positive about the potential of prediction markets if we will somehow resolve the legal problems (which seems unrealistic in the short term but realistic in the medium term).  Here is my perspective on "why should a normie who is somewhat risk-averse, don't enjoy wagering for its own sake, and doesn't care about the information externalities, engage with prediction markets" First, let me try to tackle the question at face value: 1. "A normie" can describe a large social group, but it's too general to describe a single person. You can be a normie, but maybe you work at a Toyota dealership. Maybe you just accidentally overheard that the head of your department was talking on the phone and said that recently there were major problems with hydrogen cars which are likely to delay deployment by a few years. If there is a prediction market for hydrogen cars, you can bet and win (or at least you can think that you will win). It's relatively common among normies to think along the lines "I bought a Toyota car and it's amazing, I will buy Toyota stock and it will make me rich". Of course, such thinking is usually invalid, Toyota's quality is probably already priced in, so it's a toss of a coin if it will overperform the broader market or not. Overall, it's probably not a bad idea to buy Toyota stock, but some people do it not because it's an ok idea but because they think it's an amazing idea. I expect the same dynamics to play in prediction markets. 2. Even if you don't enjoy "wagering for its own sake", prediction markets can be more than mere wagering.  Although it's a bit similar in spirit, gamification is applicable to prediction markets, for example, Manifold is doing it pretty successfully (from my perspective as an active user, it's quite addictive) although it hasn't led to substantial user growth yet. Even the wagering itself can be different -- you can bet "all on black" because you desperatel

Any position that could be considered safe enough to back a market is only going to appreciate in proportion to inflation, which would just make the market zero-sum after adjusting for inflation. Something like ETH or gold wouldn't be a good solution because it's going to be massively distorted on questions that are correlated with the performance of that asset, plus there's always the possibility that they just go down, which would be the opposite of what you want.

1Qumeric
Why does it have to be "safe enough"? If all market participants agree to bet using the same asset, it can bear any degree of risk.  I think I should have said that a good prediction market allows users to choose what asset will a particular "pair" use. It will cause a liquidity split which is also a problem, but it's also manageable and, in my opinion, it would be much closer to an imaginary perfect solution than "bet only USD".  I am not sure I understand your second sentence, but my guess is that this problem will also go away if each market "pair" uses a single (but customizable) asset. If I got it wrong, could you please clarify?

Christopher King

20

A lot of the money comes from the bad traders. If you have no bad traders, the prices are correct.

A better mechanism though is to "subsidize the market", meaning the person who wants the information incentives the market to collect it. In particular, you can set up subsidy schemes where the average cost to the subsidizer is proportional to the number of bits of information they gained.

6 comments, sorted by Click to highlight new comments since:

A lot of commentary here confuses individual returns with improving information.  Stocks generally have returns from business, and this is important to information-free investors.  But those don't matter for info purposes.  Even in the stock market, all of the information value about where to direct capital comes from those trying to BEAT the market.  Those with opinions backed by money making individual relative decisions.  The masses buying indices or simple spreads don't actually increase the effectiveness of capital allocation.

Prediction markets have a "market average" of 0.  There is no reason to buy a prediction index fund, and no benefit to the market if someone did so.  

Predictions ONLY have information value - if you can make better predictions than the average, you get paid when it resolves, and you improve the accuracy in the meantime.  If you make worse predictions, you lose money.  It's really that simple.

But it's easy to forget, in the comparison with stocks, that "participation" means making and standing behind predictions, not just putting money in.

But all the people putting money into stocks, provide the market makers for the people with better information to make money.

Nope, that's my point.  MOST people putting money into stocks are NOT providing any information.  They're just buying a fund or following general rules that don't deviate from aggregate measures or move any part of the market relative to others.

Those who are seriously attempting to BEAT the market are giving actual price signals about how their beliefs differ from the current average.

I think Yair is saying that the people putting in money randomly is what allows "beat the market" to be profitable. Isn't the return on beating the market proportional to the size of the market? In which case, if more people put money into the prediction markets suboptimally, this would be a moneymaking opportunity for professional forecasters, and you could get more/better information from the prediction markets.

At least ignoring legislation, an exchange could offer a contract with the same return as S&P 500 (for the aggregate of a pair of traders entering a Kalshi-style event contract); mechanistically, this index-tracking could be supported by just using the money put into a prediction market to buy VOO and selling when the market settles. (I think.)