I think this post is pretty cool, and represents good groundwork on sticky questions of bioethics and the principles that should underpin them that most people don't think about very hard. Thanks for writing it.
I noticed that this focuses on the liberty of parents, and it is not a general framework for all genetic engineering
I don't think these liberties for parents should cleanly extend to non-germline gene engineering
In those cases we would expect these liberties to lie with the modified person
I think we can identify how this is an extension of the idea that parents are empowered to pre-emptively make decisions for their children that those children, once adult, should have the right to make for themselves (eg. as an adult you have rights to decide where to live, (insofar as this is limited by immigration law and by availiblity of jobs and housing), as a child your parents decide where you will live and be born) and the idea that people should have lots of power over themselves (including the right for significant body modification)
Ah, yeah, that's a good clarification. I definitely had in mind specifically altering future children, i.e. making a single cell with a vectored genome and then making a baby from that cell.
I haven't thought too much about somatic gene therapy. I think it's probably, from a technical side, mostly worse (less safe, less effective) than germline engineering. With germline engineering, you can make the genome of the future child be safe as a genome (e.g. basically indistinguishable from a natural genome); with somatic engineering you're doing some very weird thing that's not found in nature and that is hard to check the results of (e.g. CRISPR editor uptake would be different in different tissues). I mean it could be fine; but for germline engineering, you'll be able to make a nearly iron-clad argument that it's fine.
Your right that in principle somatic gene engineering is probably harder (especially once you consider the complexity of human maturation means that some things are hard to change)
I would not discount it, however
you have 15-20 years of time between germline engineering and an adult person, and in that time somatic engineering has time to catch up, and another 60-80 years after that if you are lucky before that person would die with current lifespans. In those 80-100 years, somatic engineering can catch up, and allow for revectoring
I am fairly certain that it is likely that people will be doing both. If you really bottle germline, but get a functional result with something unacceptable like 20 year fatal cancer risks at 70-90% (unlikely but possible), somatic can get a second bite at the apple.
Doing things that would cut that off might be unwise/unethical.
This is a thoughtful post, and I appreciate it. I don't think I disagree with it from a liberty perspective, and agree there are potential huge benefits for humanity here.
However, my honest first reaction is "this reasoning will be used to justify a world in which citizens of rich countries have substantially superior children to citizens of poor countries (as viewed by both groups)". These days, I'm much more suspicious of policies likely to be socially corrosive: it leads to bad governance at a time where, because of AI risk, we need excellent governance.
I'm sure you've thought about this question, it's the classic objection. Do you have any idea how to avoid or at least mitigate the inequality adopting genomic liberty would cause? Or do you think it wouldn't happen at all? Or do you think that it's simply worth it and natural that any new technology is first adopted by those who can afford it, and that adoption drives down prices and will spread the technology widely soon enough?
this reasoning will be used to justify a world in which citizens of rich countries have substantially superior children to citizens of poor countries (as viewed by both groups)
I'm not quite sure I follow. Let me check. You might be saying:
Genomic liberty says that people should be free to make genomic choices, and that states should regulate this only minimally, and in particular that international governance shouldn't prevent states from using germline engineering.
Or maybe you're saying:
Spiritually, genomic liberty is individualistic / localistic; it says that if some individual or group or even state (at a policy level, as a large group of individuals) wants to use germline engineering technology, it is good for them to do so, regardless of whether others are using it. Thus, it justifies unequal access, saying that a world with unequal access is still a good world.
To be kinda precise and narrow, the narrow meaning of genomic liberty as a negative right doesn't say it's good or even ok to have worlds with unequal access. As a moral claim, it more narrowly says
For the great majority of ways people will use germline engineering, that use will be not so morally abhorrent that we should use state force to prevent that use, given the high moral cost of curtailing reproductive genomic autonomy.
This does say something about the unequal world--namely that it's "not so morally abhorrent that we should [have international regulation backed by the threat of war] to prevent that use". I don't think that's a ringing endorsement.
I'm sure you've thought about this question, it's the classic objection.
To be honest, mainly I've thought about inequality within single economic and jurisdictional regimes. (I think that objection is more common than the international version.) I'm not even sure how to orient to international questions--practically, morally, and conceptually. Probably I'd want to have at least a tiny bit of knowledge about other international relations (conflicts, law, treaties, cooperative projects, aid, long-term development) before thinking about this much. I'm unclear on the ethics of one country doing something that doesn't harm other countries in any direct way, and even directly helps other coutries at least on first-order; but also doesn't offer that capability to other countries especially vigorously.
Certainly, personally, I take a humanist and universalist stance: It is good for all people to be empowered; it is bad for some group to try to have some enduring advantage over others by harming or suppressing the others or even by permanently withholding information that would help them.
It does seem good to think about the international question. I'm unsure whether it should ultimately be a crux, though.
I do think it's better if germline engineering is developed in the US before, say, Russia, because the US will work out the liberal version, and will be likely to be generous with the technology in the long-run.
Or do you think it wouldn't happen at all?
It would almost certainly happen to a significant extent.
Or do you think that it's simply worth it and natural that any new technology is first adopted by those who can afford it, and that adoption drives down prices and will spread the technology widely soon enough?
Right, this is a big part of what I hope, and somewhat expect, and want to aim for. I am however curious to hear examples of technologies that
(So, "superyachts" doesn't count, because obviously it's expensive to make a seaworthy building; "super complex medical treatment" may or may not count depending on what fundamental barriers there are to inexpensivizing and whether there even are that many people it would treat. One might have to have different expected curves for within- vs. between-countries. )
Do you have any idea how to avoid or at least mitigate the inequality adopting genomic liberty would cause?
So, to some extent we want to make the technology end up cheap and effective. A big part of this is looking for strong GV methods:
GV strength is generally interchangeable with cutting costs. Cutting costs is crucial for making GV technology widely available, in order to have the greatest benefit and to prevent problems with inequality.
Another part is spreading the ideology that everyone should have access. I think the US is a great starting place because we're a diverse country (ethnically, ideologically, culturally, religiously, and in terms of country of ancestors). So maybe developing the tech here binds it up with "all people should have this". Maybe I'm confused how culture works though, I'm just making this up, and of course very many people do not think this way. (To the extent that I personally push this tech forward, which realistically won't be very much in all likelihood, hopefully I'd also have some kind of voice.)
The ideology should get a separate treatment--genomic liberty but as a positive right--what I've been calling genomic emancipation.
Thanks for the detailed response!
Re: my meaning, you got it correct here:
Spiritually, genomic liberty is individualistic / localistic; it says that if some individual or group or even state (at a policy level, as a large group of individuals) wants to use germline engineering technology, it is good for them to do so, regardless of whether others are using it. Thus, it justifies unequal access, saying that a world with unequal access is still a good world.
Re: genomic liberty makes narrow claims, yes I agree, but my point is that if implemented it will lead to a world with unequal access for some substantial period of time, and that I expect this to be socially corrosive.
Switching to quoting your post and responding to those quotes:
To be honest, mainly I've thought about inequality within single economic and jurisdictional regimes. (I think that objection is more common than the international version.)
Yeah that's the common variant of the concern but I think it's less compelling - rich countries will likely be able to afford subsidizing gene editing for their citizens, and will be strongly incentivized to do so even if it's quite expensive. So my expectation is that the intra-country effects for rich countries won't be as bad as science fiction has generally predicted, but that the international effects will be.
(and my fear is this would play into general nationalizing trends worldwide that increase competition and make nation-states bitter towards each other, when we want international cooperation on AI)
I am however curious to hear examples of technologies that {snip}
My worry is mostly that the tech won't spread "soon enough" to avoid socially corrosive effects, less so that it will never spread. As for a tech that never fully spread but should have benefitted everyone, all that comes to mind is nuclear energy.
So maybe developing the tech here binds it up with "all people should have this".
I think this would happen, but it would be expressed mostly resentfully, not positively.
The ideology should get a separate treatment--genomic liberty but as a positive right--what I've been calling genomic emancipation.
Sounds interesting!
As for a tech that never fully spread but should have benefitted everyone, all that comes to mind is nuclear energy.
Thanks for the example. I think nuclear is a special case (though lots of cases are special in different ways): It takes a pretty large project to start up; and it comes with nuclear proliferation, which is freaky because of bombs.
I think this would happen, but it would be expressed mostly resentfully, not positively.
Wait, I'm confused; I thought we both think it's at least fairly likely to go well within the US, i.e. lots of people and diverse people have access. So then they can say "it is good, and we are happy about it and want it to be shared, or at least are not going to seriously impede that". (Call me pollyanna if you want lol, but that's kinda what I mainline expect I think?)
....Oh is this also referring to countries being resentful? Hm... Possibly I should be advocating for the technology to not be embargoed/withheld by the federal government (like some military technology is)?
Yeah referring to international sentiments. We'd want to avoid a "chip export controls" scenario, which would be tempting I think.
Other points:
There are diminishing returns and a ceiling on gains. The ceiling is quite high, but it's there. You can only decrease disease risk to "roughly 0", and this probably happens with medium-strength engineering (vaguely speaking); longevity probably (I speculate) has some caps coming from aging processes that aren't fixed using genetic variants existing in the population; and IQ can't be safely pushed way outside the human range. This means that countries could get ahead, but probably not crazy-ahead, and in the long run it should be easier to catch up than to pull ahead farther. (Ok this isn't clear because maybe a head start on intelligence amplification snowballs or something.)
Uptake will start slow. It will speed up when people see how good the results are. But that information will be available to roughly everyone at roughly the same time: everyone sees the exceptionally healthy, capable kids at the same time, wherever those kids were. So for the big ramp-up, part that would matter on a national-national scale, there's less of a head start. (There's still probably serial lead time for some elements, but who knows.)
I do think there's significant risk of inequality between ancestry groups, which relates to states though not one to one. That's because there's quite large inequalities between how much genomic data has been collected for different groups (see e.g. here: https://gwasdiversitymonitor.com/, though this is about GWASes, not exactly genomic data). Current PGSes don't translate between groups very well. One way to address this is of course to gather more diverse data. (But the situation might not be so bad: plausibly once you more accurately identify which genetic variants are causal, your PGSes generalize between groups much better, or it takes much less additional data from the group to make scores that generalize.)
This seems like an argument that proves too much; ie, the same argument applies equally to childhood education programs, improving nutrition, etc. The main reason it doesn't work is that genetic engineering for health and intelligence is mostly positive-sum, not zero-sum. Ie, if people in one (rich) country use genetic engineering to make their descendents smarter and the people in another (poor) country don't, this seems pretty similar to what has already happened with rich countries investing in more education, which has been strongly positive for everyone.
Good objection. I think gene editing would be different because it would feel more unfair and insurmountable. That's probably not rational - the effect size would have to be huge for it to be bigger than existing differences in access to education and healthcare, which are not fair or really surmountable in most cases - but something about other people getting to make their kids "superior" off the bat, inherently, is more galling to our sensibilities. Or at least mine, but I think most people feel the same way.
Important, and would be nice even if passed as-is! Admittedly, there's some space to have even stronger ideas, like...
"Confidentiality of genomic interventions. Human has natural right for details of which aspects of their genome were custom-chosen, if any, to be kept confidential" (probably also prohibit parents/guardians from disclosing that, since knowledge cannot be sealed back into the box).
PDF version. berkeleygenomics.org. Twitter thread. (Bluesky copy.)
Summary
The world will soon use human germline genomic engineering technology. The benefits will be enormous: Our children will be long-lived, will have strong and diverse capacities, and will be halfway to the end of all illness.
To quickly bring about this world and make it a good one, it has to be a world that is beneficial, or at least acceptable, to a great majority of people. What laws would make this world beneficial to most, and acceptable to approximately all? We'll have to chew on this question ongoingly.
Genomic Liberty is a proposal for one overarching principle, among others, to guide public policy and legislation around germline engineering. It asserts:
If upheld, genomic liberty protects the rights of parents from regulation by the state.
A visual summary of the more detailed structure of the principle of genomic liberty:
The principle of genomic liberty has several potential exceptions. These cases aren't strongly protected by genomic liberty, and therefore could potentially be regulated while upholding genomic liberty:
Within the principle of genomic liberty, there are tentpole principles that apply to a narrower set of cases, but that give stronger protection against regulation. These tentpole principles help to clarify genomic liberty, and to fortify it against inappropriate regulation:
Non-intervention liberty. Parents have a very strong right to not genomically intervene on their child, in whole or in any aspect.
Propagative liberty. Parents have a strong right to propagate their own genes and their own traits, in whole or in some aspects.
Typicalization liberty. Parents have a strong right to move their future child closer, in expectation, to the median value of one or more traits.
Beneficent liberty. Parents have a strong right to make well-informed genomic choices that a reasonable person would agree are aimed at giving their child a life of wellbeing.
Altruistic liberty. Parents have a strong right to make well-informed genomic choices that a reasonable person would agree are aimed at giving their child a life that would contribute to the wellbeing of others.
The remainder of the article expands on this summary.
My hope is to start a conversation in which we seriously envision this coming world and think about how to make it a good one.
Statement of the principle
To restate the principle of genomic liberty a bit more precisely:
The principle of genomic liberty isn't saying that any specific choices you might make about your child's genome are morally good or bad. Rather, genomic liberty is a political principle, like the principle of the freedom of speech. It says that parents are, by right, the primary decision-makers about the genomes of their own children. Therefore, states should ensure that parents have wide, protected latitude within the law to influence the genomes of their children, in whole or in some aspects, if they wish. Anomaly, Gyngell, and Savulescu (2020)[1] suggest applying "regulatory parsimony"[2] to the question of regulating genomic choices; to some extent this agrees in spirit with the regulatory stance mandated by the principle of genomic liberty.
(For more elaboration on the nature of the principle, see the appendix "Genomic liberty is a political principle".)
Like any principle, genomic liberty is not simple and absolute. It competes with other principles and practicalities, and therefore it has exceptions which have to be carved out. In order to be strongly upheld as a right, genomic liberty should be protected by clarifying and codifying its concrete instances. That is the aim of the rest of this article.
Disclaimers
I know next to nothing about law and public policy. So this article is speculation from a layman's perspective, and might therefore contain obvious blunders. I am out of my depth, here; and I've felt conflicted about several of the points proposed here. My opinions will change.
My hope with this proposal is to nucleate discussion and eventually lead to better thought-out policies. This proposal only even attempts to partially address one element—the overarching public policy principles—out of many elements of a good future societal stance towards germline engineering.
This article is not mainly meant to make the case for genomic liberty, and does not present an overall argument. It is mainly meant to present a proposal for what the principle of genomic liberty should mean in the first place. I do make some arguments, mainly in order to explain why this proposal is specifically the way it is, rather than being some other similar proposal.
This article is produced by precautionary foresight about a technology and societal situation that does not exist yet. Therefore, it is not well-grounded in empirical observation of the outcomes in question or in the practicalities of law and law enforcement. Also, it will focus on difficult and in many cases somewhat alarming scenarios, in order to deal with them; but remember that, by and large, the technology will be greatly beneficial to the great majority of users making free, reasonable enough choices.
Analogy: First Amendment rights
Consider, for comparison, the principle of the freedom of thought. This principle is codified in the First Amendment of the US constitution:
The throughline of the First Amendment rights is freedom of thought. James Madison, in his address to the House of Representatives introducing a draft Bill of Rights, even suggested as part of religious protections the further protection for moral beliefs in general: "[...], nor shall the full and equal rights of conscience be in any manner, or on any pretext infringed."[4].
Although freedom of thought is a cherished keystone of free and open societies, it is far from absolute. Many people take quite strong stances defending freedom of speech, but nevertheless, almost everyone agrees that some kinds of speech should be prohibited. (Of course, there is disagreement about where to draw the line between protected and unprotected speech.)
Here's a schematic depicting this situation. The light blue oval is freedom of thought, which is protected under the First Amendment. The red ovals are some of the exceptions to freedom of thought.
The text of the First Amendment lists several rights: to religion, speech, press, assembly, and petition. Why list all these rights, instead of just a single right? Maybe the First Amendment could have read simply:
Madison explains why there are rights being explicitly declared at all:
The rising and falling tides of legislative sentiment will probe the inlets to our rights. The precious rights therefore have to be defended most strongly in those places. Freedom of thought may have been a leitmotif in the American spirit, but to be a strong right, it needed to be codified as more concrete tentpole freedoms:
These tentpole principles, enumerated in the First Amendment, are more narrow than a broad freedom of thought, but they are more clear and more strong. They are placed strategically where there may be a motive from legislators to restrict freedoms, and they protect some of the most important aspects of freedom of thought.
Exceptions to the genomic liberty principle
As with the First Amendment, genomic liberty will have exceptions. The existence of exceptions is compatible with the principle being strong. Part of clarifying the strong core of genomic liberty is the task of circumscribing it by explicitly accepting limitations on its purview of protection. What remains unexcepted is the core domain of the GL principle, which is to be strongly upheld and applied to prevent inappropriate regulation.
The following list gives some recognized exceptions to genomic liberty. These genomic choices can be banned without inappropriately contravening the genomic liberty principle.
Summary of exceptions
A schematic summary of the exceptions:
Elaboration on the list of exceptions:
Prospectively very unsafe
Substantively impinging on humanity
Extreme negative externalities
Nonconsensual DNA use
Severely non compos mentis
Permanent silencing
Additional notes on these exceptions
Tentpole principles of genomic liberty
Genomic liberty as a principle of lawmaking will be pushed against: people will try to make laws that restrict genomic choices. Some of those attempts will fall within appropriate exceptions to GL; some of those attempts will be inappropriate, and will have to be combated if the principle of genomic liberty is to be upheld.
The specific protections listed in the First Amendment uphold crucial elements of the general right to freedom of thought. Analogously, in order to weather legislative pushes appropriately, we will shore up genomic liberty with tentpole principles. As is the case with the First Amendment protections, these tentpole protected liberties are not exceptionless; but they are especially strong protections which would require very good reason to encroach upon.
A schematic summary of the tentpole principles that hold up general genomic liberty:
Elaboration on the list of tentpole principles:
Non-intervention liberty
Propagative liberty
Typicalization liberty
Beneficent liberty
Altruistic liberty
Conclusion
Genomic liberty prevents the state from unduly restricting the freedom of parents to choose the genomes of their children. This principle will defend most people's values, while the exceptions leave room to prevent hypothetically possible extreme misuses of germline engineering technology. Thus society can get the diverse and widely distributed benefits of germline engineering, without unacceptable cost.
Appendix: Some clarifications of genomic liberty
Copying the fuller statement of the GL principle:
Some clarifications:
GL is a negative right: it stands against infringement by the state or society upon the freedom of parents. To be precise, GL is spiritually aligned with, but separate from, a corresponding positive right: The right to access to technology for altering your future child's genome.
GL is meant to defend strongly against infringement by the state, but only weakly against social pressure and against professional ethics.
GL does not apply to non-human entities.
By default, GL protects genomic choices that others would consider distasteful, immoral, or even anti-social.
For example, choosing to make your male child very tall is a kind of burning of the commons: Perhaps he'll be more successful himself, but if everyone does this, no one is better off and everyone is less healthy. GL says this must not be prohibited by the state.
However, it might be correct to socially disapprove of that sort of choice. Further, self-regulatory organizations might put soft restrictions in place, e.g. requiring waiting periods, specific information being delivered to the parents, etc., to dissuade them from making choices that many perceive to be anti-social. This might be problematic in itself, but in any case it is not in the purview of GL.
For example, the moral principle of procreative beneficence as proposed by Savulescu says that "couples who decide to have a child have a significant moral reason to select the child who, given his or her genetic endowment, can be expected to enjoy the most well-being"[6:1]. I subscribe to this moral principle. However, GL would oppose this principle being codified into law as a legal obligation for parents to make specific genomic choices. A major issue with doing so is that "well-being" is hard to define, and more importantly people might have genuine differences in their vision of a good life for their children.
Another moral principle for genomic choices is procreative altruism "according to which parents have significant moral reason to select a child whose existence can be expected to contribute more to (or detract less from) the well-being of others than any alternative child they could have"[7:1]. Again, this is a true moral principle, but, according to the GL, should not be made into law.
Regarding synthetic biology in general, Gutmann (2011) suggests "regulatory parsimony"[2:2]. Anomaly, Gyngell, and Savulescu (2020), in discussing collective action problems with genomic choices, suggest applying regulatory parsimony: instead of complex regulation that gives an unclear benefit and restricts parental freedom, we can address collective action problems with social norms[1:2]. This agrees with the genomic liberty principle: There may be some harms to society due to externalities of genomic choices, but these genomic choices should not be made illegal until there's a quite strong reason to do so.
The GL principle does not protect any specific germline engineering technology or method.
GL does protect atypical family structures.
GL only applies to human DNA.
Generally, like any right, GL is a living entity, open to revision, and is not absolute.
Appendix: Genomic liberty is a political principle
Summary:
Elaboration in the following subsections:
Genomic liberty is not a moral stance on specific uses of GE
Summary:
Elaboration:
If I adopt the genomic liberty principle, then, for example, that means I must advocate for the legal right of deaf parents to alter the genome of their potential child so that the child will likely be deaf. And, I must give a minimum of social acceptance to such parents: I cannot discriminate against them in public business transactions, or coordinate social harassment to push them out of communities.
However, I can still hold the moral position that deaf parents ought not to do so. Perhaps I believe making your child deaf is immoral, on the grounds that you ought to give your child as much capacity as is feasible, or on the grounds that the child didn't consent to that atypical alteration. I can argue for that moral position, and express disapproval of people's behavior, while still upholding the political principle of genomic liberty. (In fact, personally, I'm quite undecided on the moral question, but I am decided that this choice should be a protected right.)
Of course, a political stance has to be a moral stance, to some degree. To support the genomic liberty principle is also to make a moral assertion:
Political principles support civil compromise
Summary:
Elaboration:
Needless to say, if we think some behavior is moral or immoral, that influences which laws we can and do make about the behavior, and influences which behavior we socially punish. People who believe abortion is immoral will support more restrictions on abortion, and will advocate against political candidates who support abortion rights. Murdering already-born people is very widely agreed to be highly immoral, and is therefore extra super illegal.
However, moral stances do not and should not always translate into legal regulation. There are many forms of speech that many find abhorrent, such as expressing Nazi ideology. In 1977, two Jewish lawyers from the ACLU, a civil liberties organization, famously helped to legally defend a neo-Nazi group's right to hold public demonstrations. The legal protection is upheld even for abhorrent behavior.
Furthermore, attempting to enforce a moral view through coordinated extra-judicial violence should be viewed as an extremely unacceptable breach of civil norms, even beyond being straightforwardly illegal. In order to maintain basic order, the government has a monopoly on initiating violence. The government does abuse this power, and this betrayal is extremely corrosive; but the government monopoly on initiating violence is crucial. Vigilante justice, mob violence, and coordinated illegal harassment are another betrayal of basic civil order. Such extra-judicial violence is politically and morally motivated: no one is staging illegally violent protests in order to legalize murdering already-born people, because approximately no one believes that murder is morally or socially acceptable.
Legal principles are supposed to be how we achieve a basic coordination, so that individuals and groups can live together in a country, freely and without unduly destructive conflict. Assaulting legal abortion clinics, doctors, and patients is unacceptable; political riots that destroy and disrupt public property are unacceptable; SWATing ideological Nazis is unacceptable; harassing sex workers is unacceptable. Get the law changed, or restrict yourself to non-violent opposition.
Actions that harm others are much more heavily regulated compared to actions that only harm yourself. Consuming consensually-produced pornography is legal, suicide is legal, alcohol addiction is legal. All of these are to one or another extent self-harming, and in many cases immoral, but they generally don't materially harm others enough to justify per se legal regulation.
So generally, the point of law, flowing from political policy, is a peaceful enough coexistence through resolution of conflicts with sufficient justice for all parties.
Genomic liberty as a proposed civil compromise
Summary:
Elaboration:
The use of human germline genomic engineering technology will be contentious. Many will strongly oppose using it at all. Many others will oppose any permission from the state to alter genomes. Many will strongly oppose some of its uses, e.g. parents altering their child's IQ or parents predisposing their child to dwarfism.
On the other hand, many will oppose any influence on people's reproduction from the state, as that would overlap in intention and in practice with harmful eugenic policies. Many will strongly oppose specific restrictions on the use of germline engineering. For example, some fraction of gay people might strongly wish to predispose their own child to also be gay. Some fraction of Christian people might strongly wish to predispose their own child to remain Christian through adulthood. Many such groups would have reason to oppose restrictions on their ability to propagate.
The benefits of germline engineering will be straightforwardly awesome: halfway to the end of all disease, long lives for our children, and a great flowering of many diverse human capacities. To get these benefits, we need a political policy about germline engineering that most people find acceptable.
If there were a political policy that had the state substantially infringing on people's reproductive genomic choices, that political policy would be a poor compromise. If there were lots of people who would want to choose aspects of their children's genomes, but who can't because of state regulation, those people would have reason to strongly object to the policy. Thus, the principle of genomic liberty is meant to be a central aspect of a broadly acceptable compromise policy.
Anomaly, Jonathan, Christopher Gyngell, and Julian Savulescu. ‘Great Minds Think Different: Preserving Cognitive Diversity in an Age of Gene Editing’. Bioethics 34, no. 1 (January 2020): 81–89. https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.12585. ↩︎ ↩︎ ↩︎
Gutmann, Amy. ‘The Ethics of Synthetic Biology: Guiding Principles for Emerging Technologies’. Hastings Center Report 41, no. 4 (2011): 17–22. https://doi.org/10.1002/j.1552-146X.2011.tb00118.x. ↩︎ ↩︎ ↩︎
‘U.S. Constitution - First Amendment | Resources | Constitution Annotated | Congress.Gov | Library of Congress’. Accessed 16 March 2025. https://constitution.congress.gov/constitution/amendment-1/. ↩︎
‘Founders Online: Amendments to the Constitution, [8 June] 1789’. University of Virginia Press. Accessed 16 March 2025. http://founders.archives.gov/documents/Madison/01-12-02-0126. ↩︎
Miller, Joshua D., and Donald R. Lynam. ‘Understanding Psychopathy Using the Basic Elements of Personality’. Social and Personality Psychology Compass 9, no. 5 (2015): 223–37. https://doi.org/10.1111/spc3.12170. ↩︎
Savulescu, Julian, and Guy Kahane. ‘The Moral Obligation To Create Children With The Best Chance Of The Best Life’. Bioethics 23, no. 5 (June 2009): 274–90. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8519.2008.00687.x. ↩︎ ↩︎
Douglas, Thomas, and Katrien Devolder. ‘Procreative Altruism: Beyond Individualism in Reproductive Selection’. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy: A Forum for Bioethics and Philosophy of Medicine 38, no. 4 (1 August 2013): 400–419. https://doi.org/10.1093/jmp/jht022. ↩︎ ↩︎