From your Dennett-quote at the end:
This leads some people to insist that consciousness can never be explained. But why should consciousness be the only thing that can’t be explained? Solids and liquids and gases can be explained in terms of things that aren’t themselves solids or liquids or gases. Surely life can be explained in terms of things that aren’t themselves alive — and the explanation doesn’t leave living things lifeless. The illusion that consciousness is the exception comes about, I suspect, because of a failure to understand this general feature of successful explanation. Thinking, mistakenly, that the explanation leaves something out, we think to save what otherwise would be lost by putting it back into the observer as a quale — or some other “intrinsically” wonderful property.
I want to propose that Dennett is slightly mistaken; it's not that people haven't generalised it to all the relevant cases. Many people have learned that things in their map can be explained in terms of simpler things in their map (e.g. biology, physics, psychology, etc).
However, it can be additionally hard to generalise this to the map itself, - sure, your map of your map should have some reduction (i.e. the brain is made of atoms) but does that really apply to your map, as opposed to your map of your map? People successfully generalise, but they fail to go meta.
Curated this post because:
A reason not to curate the post might have been that despite the above points, several people may nevertheless feel that it's not sufficiently connected to the topics of epistemic or instrumental rationality. However, we've got a bunch of more directly related posts in our curation queue, so in light of that and the above points, I'm curating this. (We've been slacking a little on curating posts and now have a bunch of them chosen for curation; doing it at a pace of one per day.)
Loved the review - seems like an awesome book. I recall reading it aged 13-14, where he says of chapter 6 that it is very technical and can be skipped; unfortunately I tried anyway and then never finished the book.
The most significant part of it for me was the section you describe this way:
Dennett's approach is given the mouthful of a name "heterophenomenology" (the study of other peoples' phenomena), and really means something along the lines of using reports of conscious experience as data to fill in a descriptive model of a reporter, which has room for both accurate and mistaken reports...
...in short, when interpreting text about consciousness, one tries to fit this text into an internally consistent model that is a model of the thing the text is describing.
I remember this being a big insight for me; Dennett had shown that anything that I experienced or thought about, must trace back to some real-world data that I can observe. It was a big shock to me that you could just draw something of an arbitrary line at observable data like "text that people write when we ask them about consciousness", and then propose hypotheses to explain such data.
(It wasn't until much later that I realised a good theory of consciousness should go farther and make novel predictions about what people will say in very specific situations, rather than just explaining what you have already seen. But still.)
Can anyone provide a comparison between this book and Consciousness. An Introduction - Susan Blackmore. The latter has been recommended to me, but after having read a chapter I haven't been impressed.
I can’t provide an in-depth comparison, but I have read both books, and Dennett’s was vastly superior.
Wow, this gives me a much more favorable view of Dennett. I had been of the opinion that he was both opposed to phenomenology and the existence of qualia, but in fact he is himself a phenomenologists and clearly seems to support, though would perhaps not say he does, the existence of qualia as a class of phenomena. The disagreements seem to come from two places.
First, he rejects the primacy of any phenomenological account as universal, to which I say "duh", but I realize not all phenomenologists are as epistemologically careful as me and, it seems, Dennett, so I understand how the myth of his anti-phenomenological stance has been perpetrated.
Second, he rejects qualia because it is often treated as if it were opaque. I agree, and although I try to rehabilitate qualia as a technical term for the class of phenomena that differentiate the phenomenally conscious from the not, I empathize with his choice because at other times I've done the same thing and rejected the idea that qualia might exist because it seemed to posit an explanation by introducing an epicycle.
I guess in hindsight I should be less surprised, and makes me wonder if others who seem to be mistaken based on my understanding of their work in this area like Chalmers and Searle do in fact accurately describe reality and it is only the representation of their work that has stripped the nuance that would allow me to see this.
Excellent review. Consciousness Explained is one of my favorite books of philosophy, and one of the works that cemented Dennett, in my mind, as one of the greatest contemporary philosophers of mind (and an outstanding author). It is well worth reading.
>Consider what it must have been like to be a Leipzig Lutheran churchgoer in, say, 1725, hearing one of J. S. Bach’s chorale cantatas in its premier performance.
If all the ineffability of experience comes from associations, then novel experiences should be effable-- but they are not.
There's also a really good description of ineffability in terms of Jell-O boxes that, unfortunately, I will have to butcher in order to relate. Tl;dr: If you tear a Jell-O box into two pieces, one piece will be a detector for the other - it only fits perfectly with that one shape of torn cardboard. But this property is indescribable - if you try to explain what shape it is that the piece of Jell-O box detects, you can only wave your hands at the piece of cardboard plaintively.
If all the ineffability of experience comes from complexity, then simple experiences should be effable-- but they are not.
Sorry, what's a simple experience? There's externally simple experiences like looking at a black room in the dark, but It's not like those experiences use a smaller number of neurons than my other experiences.
Experiences like seeing a single colour, or hearing a single musical tone. THe number of neurons is irrelevant, since they are not experienced.
Yeah, good point, we build models of the world, or at least of our senses, we don't automatically build models of what our neurons are doing.
(Maybe any learning in the brain can be interpreted as a "model" of the neurons that feed into the learning neurons, but the details of that sort of thing aren't available to our faculties for navigating the world, doing abstract reasoning, or communicating - they're happening at a lower layer in the software stack of the brain.)
That's veering towards a more "Mary's room" sort of definition of "ineffability," where you can't freely exchange world-models and experiences, which isn't really what the Jell-O box analogy was about - it was about interpersonal comparisons, and our inability to experience what other people experience.
But I guess they're connected. Suppose we're both listening to a simple tone, but my pitch perception is more accurate than yours. If you want to experience my experience for yourself, you might try taking your own experience and then imagining "adding on some extra pitch perception" - an act of model-to-experience exchange reminiscent of what Mary's supposed to try.
An amusingly-written critique of some of Dennett's ideas:
http://www-personal.umich.edu/~lormand/phil/cons/qualia.htm
Lormand has a better take than Dennett. Dennett thinks qualia would have to be irreducible. Lormand writes
If such arguments were convincing, they would weigh against any reductive theory of qualia. But they should not be convincing. A powerful but not dismissive response turns on distinguishing qualia properties from ways of representing them. Even if a creature has a special way of representing phenomenal properties that is unavailable to us, we can in principle objectively specify, express, or test for these phenomenal properties in other ways.
Dennett simply defines qualia overly narrowly, letting the least naturalistic philosophers own the term.
Is it weird that this theory of consciousness was, for me, comfortable reading — the sort that immediately “rings bells,” that makes us exclaim to ourselves, with something like secret pride: “Of course! I knew that all along!” ? Does that mean it's a bad theory?
There is no Cartesian Theater where "you" watch what's happening in "your brain."
Even if there was such a part of the brain, it would itself be composed of parts that aren't entirely conscious, and so none of those parts would alone be "you". There are no alternatives, besides postulating souls (or elementary particles of consciousness). The latter isn't quite apriori impossible, but if it's appealing to you, then you're doing materialism wrong.
I.
This is a book I've long been aware of, but never got that itch to read. Maybe I trusted the field of philosophy too little, assuming that a book called "Consciousness Explained" was probably not very good. Maybe I trusted the field of philosophy too much, assuming that if someone had actually explained consciousness while I was a toddler, I would have been informed somehow before now. Either way, I was wrong, and the book is great.
I'm going to try to give what is either a short tour, or a long compilation of quotes. I'm leaving out several whole chapters, nearly every thought experiment, most of the examples and science, and some very nice language. And yet, this is still long enough that I encourage you, even if you do like reading Dan Dennett on consciousness, if you don't like long things, maybe don't read this all in one sitting - stop at V or VI and pretend that's the end of part one.
II.
Dennett quickly warns the reader that he's aware that the contents may sound counterintuitive.
This is not the mysterian claim that his ideas about consciousness are likely because they are counterintuitive, but it does signal a core claim of the book: the intuitive view of the problem of consciousness is broken from the foundation up. Naturally, if the intuitive theory is wrong, the right theory is counterintuitive.
Where, exactly, is our intuition going wrong? The most important example is introduced by considering how, on macroscopic scales, it is convenient to treat observers as point-like entities:
This book might have also been called "455 Pages Of Implications Of There Being No Homuncular Observer Inside The Brain." But that probably wouldn't have sold as well. This is absolutely the most important point of the book, and it shows up again and again in different variations. There is no Cartesian Theater where "you" watch what's happening in "your brain." There is no Central Meaner who has top-down control over the meaning of what you're going to say, before it gets to your speech center. There is no Inner Senser who the brain feeds sense data to to consecrate it with consciousness. And so on and so forth.
You'd think this would get old, but the examples I gathered in the last paragraph are spread out over many chapters of neuroscience, thought experiments, and discussions of philosophical practice. Dennett spends a lot of time defending the distributed nature of the brain, and uses it to do a lot of heavy philosophical lifting, but it's always in a slightly new context, and it feels worthwhile each time.
III.
A key methodological question of the book is how to walk the line between the two extreme stances on peoples' reports of their conscious phenomena. At one extreme, one takes everything people say about their conscious experience as gospel truth. Dennett spends plenty of time impugning peoples' reliability as witnesses of their consciousness, with data and experiments such as trying to read a playing card with your peripheral vision.
At the opposite extreme, one spends all one's time explaining the reports themselves, and never seems to explain any conscious phenomena at all - the dreaded behaviorism.
Dennett's approach is given the mouthful of a name "heterophenomenology" (the study of other peoples' phenomena), and really means something along the lines of using reports of conscious experience as data to fill in a descriptive model of a reporter, which has room for both accurate and mistaken reports.
So, in short, when interpreting text about consciousness, one tries to fit this text into an internally consistent model that is a model of the thing the text is describing.
Obviously Dennett (1991) is cribbing from Yudkowsky (2008) here, as he does in various places throughout the book. Overall, I think making the reader learn the word "heterophenomenology" was worth it - the idea shows up in the book not only as a method of semi-detached intepretation, but also as a model of the sort of thing one can know about consciousness from a third-person perspective, which proves useful in taking on various philosophical puzzlers.
On the other hand, the whole thing could have been done more precisely - all these mentions of heterophenomenology rely heavily on intuition to fill in the blanks. Part of the reason why more precision was impossible is because of how heterophenomenology is used as part of Dennett's campaign of intuition pumps to try to move people from the intuitive view to a non-Cartesian view. A precise model would inspire people to ask "where's the consciousness?" as soon as it was introduced - instead, the book tries to change peoples' minds slowly.
IV.
Another point of the book, if very minor in comparison to "the model of a person as a pointlike object breaks down when you get close to them," is the difference between representeds and representings. There's a long section on the experience of events in time that trades on this distinction. In the Cartesian Theater model, the order of conscious events is uniquely determined by the order in which the events are shown onstage in the Theater. But if there's no Theater, how do we judge what order events occurred in?
The answer is that just like how we don't represent orange light on the retinas with orange-colored neurons, we don't have to to represent events that are ordered in time with neurons that are ordered in time. We use the neural equivalent of timestamps to represent time in a non-temporal way, and can compare these timestamps in a distributed way. People found this idea hard to imagine, because they imagined consciousness as if there just had to be a Cartesian Theater somewhere.
V.
What, then is Dennett's alternative picture of consciousness? He calls it the multiple drafts model, and what it is is a wholehearted embracing of the distributed nature of human minds. If you probe someone's consciousness different ways, like asking them to press a button now versus report what they remember later, you can sometimes get different answers, because the state of someone's mind is distributed throughout their brain, and different probes can access different facts about that state. It's like the thing that gets probed, which gets fixated into consciousness when we direct attention to it, has multiple drafts of itself available to different systems of the brain, and these drafts get passed around and edited as time passes.
The other key feature (perhaps you can guess) is that there really is no Central Place in the brain where the important stuff happens. Important stuff happens all over!
I think Dennett would agree that the multiple drafts model is absolutely a step in the right direction, but is also a convenient fiction, a crutch for our imagination because we're still in the process of uncovering better ways of imagining and understanding the complication of the human brain.
VI.
Thus far has only brought us to the middle of the book. Here the text becomes a little more hit and miss, and a lot less summarizable in small bites. I will resort to a list:
VII.
A story about visual perception that's too good to not reproduce:
VIII.
Dennett is somewhat infamous for denying the existence of qualia (singular: quale) - the private, ineffable stuff that makes the redness of red so red. But it's not that he denies the existence of redness - it's the private and ineffable part that's the problem.
It is in this context that Dennett says that qualia - those things on the screen in the Cartesian Theater - don't exist.
Another theme of the book that reaches its crescendo in this section is Dennett's defense of a restricted sort of un-duplicability of qualia (though of course he would never call it that), as a natural consequence of how brains work and the limits of third-person knowledge, as identified with heterophenomenology. There's more handwaving than rigorous argument supporting this, but it does seem like pretty reasonable handwaving.
There's also a really good description of ineffability in terms of Jell-O boxes that, unfortunately, I will have to butcher in order to relate. Tl;dr: If you tear a Jell-O box into two pieces, one piece will be a detector for the other - it only fits perfectly with that one shape of torn cardboard. But this property is indescribable - if you try to explain what shape it is that the piece of Jell-O box detects, you can only wave your hands at the piece of cardboard plaintively. This is a metaphor for the experience of trying to describe what it is that red looks like.
IX.
The book closes with one final piece of shameless plagiarism from the heyday of LessWrong.